First
days of a logic course[1]
Los primeros días de un curso de lógica
John Corcoran
corcoran@buffalo.edu
University at Buffalo
Buffalo,
NY, USA
Fecha de recepción: 10-03-17
Fecha de aceptación: 13-06-17
Corcoran, J. (2017). First days of a logic course.
Quadripartita Ratio: Revista de Retórica y Argumentación, 2(4), 2-11. ISSN: 2448-6485
[02]
Abstract: This short paper sketches one logician’s opinion of some basic ideas that should be presented on the first days of any logic course. It treats the nature and goals of logic. It discusses what a student can hope to achieve through study of logic. And it warns of problems and obstacles a student will have to overcome or learn to live with. It introduces several key terms that a student will encounter in logic.
A proposition is either true or false per se, not “for this or that person”. An argument is either valid or invalid per se, not “for this or that person”. An argumentation is either conclusive or inconclusive, not per se, but for a person.
However, that a given argumentation is conclusive for a given person is undeniably a matter of that person’s subjective thoughts—but only in certain respects: if a given argumentation is conclusive for one person but not for another, the first knows something the second doesn’t know. And not every argumentation thought by a given person to be conclusive for that person actually is conclusive for that person. There is more to an argumentation’s conclusiveness than subjectivity.
Suggested readings are given in parenthetical citations keyed to the References list.
Keywords: Logic, Argumentation, Begging-the-question, Demonstration, Deduction.
Resumen: En este corto artículo se bosqueja la opinión
de un lógico sobre ciertas ideas básicas que deberían explicarse en los
primeros días de cualquier curso de lógica. Se aborda la naturaleza y los objetivos
de la lógica. Se discute lo que un estudiante puede esperar lograr estudiando
lógica y se [03] advierte sobre los
problemas y obstáculos que tendrá que vencer o con los cuales tendrá que
aprender a vivir. Se introduce una buena cantidad de términos clave que un
estudiante encontrará en lógica.
Una proposición es o verdadera o falsa per se, no “para esta o aquella persona”. Un argumento es o válido o inválido per se, no “para esta o aquella persona”. Una argumentación es o concluyente o no concluyente, no per se, sino para una persona.
Sin embargo, el hecho de que una
argumentación dada sea concluyente para una persona determinada depende sin
lugar a dudas de las ideas subjetivas de tal persona, pero sólo hasta cierto
punto: si una argumentación dada es concluyente para alguien pero no para otro,
el primero sabe algo que el segundo no sabe; y no toda argumentación que
alguien en específico considere concluyente para tal persona es en realidad
concluyente para tal persona. En el carácter concluyente de una argumentación
hay más cosas involucradas que sólo la subjetividad.
Se proporcionan lecturas sugeridas en las
referencias parentéticas, ligadas con la bibliografía final.
Palabras clave: Lógica, Argumentación, Petición de principio, Demostración, Deducción.
Introduction
On the first day of a logic course,
the teacher should remind the students that most words are ambiguous (have
more than one meaning): the two five-letter words ‘logic’ and ‘proof’
are used in multiple senses even in a
logic course. The senses recommended here are not the only useful choices:
students should know this to be able to benefit from other logicians. And even
in logic attention to the figurative/literal distinction pays handsome
dividends. Moreover, italics, single quotes, and double quotes are used to mark
different important distinctions. Students should be encouraged to ask about
terminology so that it will serve them and not intimidate them (Corcoran,
1999b; 2009; and 2016).
The teacher should also emphasize
that the subject many of us call logic
was developed by human beings and that it is still being developed. Logic is
not settled, not even to the extent that number theory is. Competent,
established modern logicians disagree on fundamental points although there are
significant areas of wide agreement. Over the years new generations of
logicians renovated and expanded the work of their predecessors. Many—but not
all—propositions believed to be true by earlier logicians are disbelieved by many modern logicians.
Besides, historians of logic are continually reinterpreting the records left by
earlier logicians (Corcoran, 2010a).
Logic was developed by human beings
in response to human needs. Especially important among such needs is the need
to be able to distinguish (genuine) proofs
from bogus “proofs”: to tell conclusive argumentations
from fallacious argumentations.
Proofs are also known as demonstrations. Every proof has a true conclusion; many a “proof” has a false
conclusion. There is no way to prove a false proposition. But most importantly,
the teacher should patiently explain in general terms what a proof is, how a
proof is made, and how an attempt to make a proof can go wrong. Logic is
primarily about proofs. More exactly, the nature of proofs is one of the things
logic is about. Without focus on proofs, logic would be empty.
A logic course should respond to
student needs. Learning logic requires discipline, patience, objectivity, and
focus. But the humanistic and spiritual nature of logic should not be left out
(Corcoran, 1989b; Corcoran & Frank, 2013).
[04]
In founding logic, Aristotle built on
the Socratic distinction between believing
a proposition to be true and knowing
that it is true: the belief-knowledge distinction. Proof produces knowledge, not just belief, not opinion. Persuasion produces opinion, belief that is not knowledge.
My knowledge consists of my beliefs that I know
to be true. My opinions are my beliefs that I do not know to be true (Corcoran, 2006a; Corcoran & Hamid, 2015).
Every proposition is either true or false per se. Not every proposition
is either known to be true or known to be false by a given person. The famous Goldbach Hypothesis is one of many counterexamples to the proposition that every proposition is either
known to be true by someone or known to be false by someone (Corcoran, 2005,
2017).
An argumentation is a three-part system composed of a “premise set”, a
“conclusion”, and a step-by-step “chain-of-reasoning”. In order for an
argumentation to be conclusive, to be a proof (of its conclusion to a given
group of people), it is necessary and
sufficient for the premises to be known to be true (by the group, by every
member) and for its chain-of-reasoning to show (to the group) that its conclusion is a logical consequence of its premises.
To be a proof (of its conclusion to a given group of people) it is necessary but not sufficient for an
argumentation to have all true premises and to have a true conclusion implied by the premises. In order for an
argumentation to be inconclusive (fallacious or be a bogus “proof”) (to a
given group of people) it is necessary and sufficient either for its premises
to be not all known to be true (by the group) or for its
chain-of-reasoning to not show (to the group) that its conclusion is a logical
consequence of its premises. Every fallacious “proof” has faulty premises or
faulty reasoning. To be fallacious in this sense, it is sufficient but not necessary for an argumentation to have a false
premise or a conclusion not implied by the premises (Corcoran, 1989a).
An argumentation is cogent (to a given group of people) if
its chain-of-reasoning shows (to the group) that its conclusion is a logical
consequence of its premises, non-cogent otherwise. To be a proof (of its
conclusion to a given group of people) it is necessary but not sufficient for an argumentation to be cogent (to
the group). Critical evaluation of an
argumentation to determine whether it is a proof for a given person reduces to
two basic issues: are the premises known to be true by the given person? And
does the chain of reasoning deduce the conclusion from the premise-set for the
given person?
This is not a relativist or subjectivist
view of proof: if a given argumentation is a proof to one person but fallacious
to another, then the first has objective knowledge that the second lacks
(Corcoran & Hamid, 2014).
What is logic about?
As said, logic is primarily about
proof. In its quest to understand proof, logic involves everything that must be
understood to understand proof. Again as said, logic presupposes the Socratic
distinction between believing a proposition to be true and knowing that it is
true: the belief-knowledge distinction. Not every proposition believed to be
true is really true. But every proposition known to be true is really true.
Every proposition proved to be true is known to be true.
Logic is about proof—not persuasion,
and not faith. Persuasion is studied in rhetoric—a
field that needs logic as much as mathematics needs logic. Before a proof can
be started, we must have in mind a “conclusion” to be proved and we must have
in mind the “premise set” that the proof will be based on. The conclusion is
often a proposition believed or conjectured but not known to be true. Proof
often transforms opinion into knowledge. The propositions in the premise set
must be known to be true by anyone who will be able to possess the argumentation as a proof.
In the context of a first course in
logic, it would be natural to say that logic is proof theory, the theory of
proof, just as it is natural to call arithmetic number theory, the theory of
numbers. But the two-word expression ‘proof theory’ has been given a much
narrower meaning in advanced logic [05] where it denotes, not a study of
proofs, but a study of character strings some of which can be taken to be
descriptions of proofs (Corcoran, 1973: 28f; and Corcoran, Frank & Maloney,
1974: 625ff).
Every so often we need to remind
students that we are not infallible, but that doesn’t mean we don’t have
knowledge. Moreover, students need reminding that we sometimes get carried away
a tad and that we sometimes need to fudge (Corcoran, 1999b).
Begging-the-question
One obvious fact about any actual
proof is that its premises are known to be true by those who possess it: those
for whom it is a proof. The premises are “established fact”.
The fallacy of accepting as a proof
an argumentation whose premises are not known to be true is traditionally
called begging-the-question. It is
not to the point to say how the tradition got started but it does help students
to note that this bizarre expression does not use either the word ‘begging’ or
the word ‘question’ in their most familiar senses. I hyphenate it to encourage
students to understand it as a unitary expression whose meaning is not derived
from the meanings of its parts.
Begging-the-question includes but is
not exhausted by “assuming what is to be proved”, as long as ‘assuming’ means
“explicitly or implicitly taking as a premise for purposes of proving”
(Corcoran & Frank, 2015). There is something perverse about using the
etymologically obscure expression ‘begging-the-question’ for “assuming what is
to be proved” in the above sense if only because the latter fallacy already has
a clear name: circular reasoning.
Besides there is nothing wrong about assuming what is to be proved per se: we often try to understand a
proposition better by assuming it in the process of deducing its consequences.
In fact, this is a key step in the method
of analysis: a method for discovering proofs (Corcoran, 1979).
In order to serve as premises of a
person’s proof, propositions must be known to be true by that person: a proof
can use propositions now known to be true to gain knowledge of a conclusion not
now known to be true (Corcoran, 1989a).
This fallacy has other names as well
but it is far more often called ‘begging-the-question’ than called anything
else. Many people who do not understand proof use the ambiguous expression
‘begging-the-question’ only in other
senses. Those who insist on using ‘begging-the-question’ in any other way
should be prepared to say what they call this
fallacy, which is one of the most important fallacies—if it is not the most
important fallacy. It is surely the most general material fallacy. It deserves a familiar name. Alternatives to
‘begging-the-question’ include the following: ‘faulty assumption (or premise)’,
‘unwarranted assumption’, ‘uncertain assumption’, and ‘unsecured basis’—none of
which have the connotation or impact carried by ‘begging-the-question’.
To avoid this fallacy, check your
premises. Taking possession of a proof requires effort.
The English language conveniently
enables us to distinguish between having
proof of (including sufficient
evidence for) a proposition and having a
proof (demonstration) of a proposition. We have proof of any proposition we
know to be true regardless of whether we have a proof of it. Knowers necessarily have proof of all of the premises of
their proofs, even if all of those premises are self-evident truths lacking
proofs. A truth is self-evident to a
knower if that knower does not need a proof, i.e., if that knower knows it without a proof—by “looking at the
fact”. Such knowledge is non-demonstrative. In ideal cases, a person who knows
a self-evident truth has proof but not a proof. Of course, it can happen that a
person who knows a truth without a proof may later find a proof. And
conversely, it can happen that a person who knows a truth by means of a proof
may later find non-demonstrative proof. A deduction having a premise lacking
proof is not a demonstration: as said above, taking such a deduction as a proof
is committing the fallacy known by logicians as begging-the-question (Corcoran,
1989a). Discussion of begging-the-question and self-evident truths provides
another opportunity to remind students [06] about ambiguity. Expressions
similar to technical terms in logic are used outside of logic with different
meanings: In logic ‘beg-the-question’ doesn’t mean ‘raises the question’ or
‘evades the question’; ‘self-evident’ doesn’t mean ‘obvious’, ‘unquestionable’,
or ‘trivial’.
Knowledge Neutrality of Deduction
Another point to be made about proofs
is that the same process of deduction used
to infer the conclusion from
established truths is also used to deduce
conclusions from premises not known to be true or even from premises known to
be false. Deduction produces knowledge of implication of a conclusion by
premises. Inferences, i.e., proofs,
are deductions from premises known to be true. Inferences, in addition, produce
knowledge of a conclusion’s truth (Corcoran, 2006b).
In a slogan: demonstration produces
knowledge of truth; deduction produces knowledge of implication.
An argument (more fully, a premise-conclusion
argument) is a two-part system composed of a set of propositions and a
single proposition: its “premises” and its “conclusion”. Every argument is
completely determined by its premises and its conclusion. Here are three
arguments in the same logical form.
Argument 1 |
Argument 2 |
Argument 3 |
Every square is a rectangle. |
Every quadrangle is a square. |
Every triangle is a rectangle. |
No rectangle is a circle. |
No square is a rhombus. |
No rectangle is a square. |
No square is a circle. |
No quadrangle is a rhombus. |
No triangle is a square. |
One way of inferring the conclusion of argument 1 from its premises involves
“looking at an arbitrary square”. But there are many other chains-of-reasoning from
those premises to that conclusion. Every one of the processes of deduction that
could have been used to infer the
true conclusion of argument 1 from its known true premises could also have been
used to deduce the false conclusion
of argument 2 from its premises, one of which is false. Likewise the same
processes of deduction could have been used to deduce the true conclusion of
argument 3 from its false premises.
Some people try to make this point by
saying that logicians do not care whether the premises are true. Apart from the
absurdity of what is said about logicians, the point is not even about
logicians: it is about implication. Here ‘implication’ refers to the relation
of premises to any conclusion implicit in them, that is, to any conclusion that
conveys no information not conveyed by the premises. Deduction produces
knowledge of implication; deduction is information processing, the process of
coming to know that the information conveyed by the conclusion is already
conveyed by the premises (Corcoran, 1996).
Direct deductions
As we saw, every argument is
completely determined by its premises and its conclusion. In the sense often
used in logic but rarely used elsewhere, recall that an argument is a two-part system composed of a set of propositions and
a single proposition: its premises and its conclusion. Again in the sense often
used in logic but rarely used elsewhere, an argument is valid if the conclusion follows from its premises, invalid otherwise. In contrast, over and
above the premises and conclusion, every proof has a chain-of-reasoning that
shows that the (final) conclusion
follows
Content-Correspondence Table
|
[07]
logically from the premises. There
are many different proofs with the same conclusion and the same premises but different
chains-of-reasoning.
There are many kinds of proof. But it
is instructive to look at the two simple types of proof that Aristotle studied:
the direct and the indirect (Corcoran, 2009b).
A direct proof based on three
premises p1, p2, and p3 and having a chain-of-reasoning with three intermediate
conclusions ic1, ic2, and ic3 can be pictured as below. The final conclusion fc occurs twice: once as a goal to be reached and then as
an accomplished goal. Some intermediate conclusions can equally well be called
intermediate premises. Since every proof is a deduction of its conclusion from
its premises, the same picture illustrates a deduction.
Three-premise Four-step
Direct Deduction Schema
p1
p2
p3
?fc
ic1
ic2
ic3
fc
Direct deduction 1
1. Every square is a rectangle.
2. Every rectangle is a polygon.
3. No circle is a polygon.?
No square is a circle.
4. No polygon is a circle. 3
5. Every rectangle is a polygon. 2
6. No rectangle is a circle. 5, 4
7. Every square is a rectangle. 1
8. No square is a circle. 7, 6
QED
Indirect deductions
An indirect proof based on three
premises p1, p2, and p3 and having a chain-of-reasoning with three intermediate
conclusions ic1, ic2, and ic3 can be pictured as below. After the final
conclusion has been set forth as a goal, an exact contradictory opposite *fc called the reductio assumption
is added as a new assumption. Taking @ to mean “assume (for purposes of
reasoning)”, the first line after the goal is @*fc,
where a contradictory opposite of the conclusion is assumed as an auxiliary
“premise”.
From the premises augmented by the reductio
assumption, intermediate conclusions are deduced until the reasoner
notes that the last intermediate conclusion, ic3 in this example, contradicts one
of the previous “lines”—often one of the premises, sometimes a previous
intermediate conclusion, sometimes even the reductio assumption, and, in very
rare cases, itself, when the last intermediate conclusion is a
self-contradiction such as “one is not one”. The fact that the reader notes the
contradiction is often expressed by writing the words ‘This is a
contradiction’, ‘A contradiction’ or even just ‘Contradiction’. Here in our
diagram we use X, the capital ecks.
Three-premise Four-step
Indirect Deduction Schema
p1
p2
p3
?fc
@*fc
ic1
ic2
ic3
X
QED
Indirect Deduction 1
1. Every square is a rectangle.
2. Every rectangle is a polygon.
3. Some circle is not a polygon.? Some circle is not a square.
4. Assume every circle is a square.
5. Every circle is a rectangle. 4, 1
6. Every circle is a polygon. 5, 2
7. But, some circle is not a polygon. 3
8. Contradiction. 7, 6
QED
[08]
The fallacy of accepting as a proof
an argumentation whose chain-of-reasoning does not establish that the conclusion
follows from the premises could be called ‘begging-the-deduction’. But it is
called faulty reasoning, fallacious chain-of-reasoning, fallacious derivation, or non-cogent derivation. This is the most
general formal fallacy. To avoid the fallacy
of faulty reasoning: check your individual steps of reasoning, make sure you
used only your stated premises, and make sure your chain-of-reasoning reached
your proposed conclusion—and not some other proposition.
Not every argumentation thought to be a proof actually is a proof
As said above, in order for an
argumentation to be a proof (of its conclusion to a given group of people) it
is necessary and sufficient for the premises to be known to be true (by the
group) and for its chain-of-reasoning to show (to the group) that its
conclusion is a logical consequence of its premises.
Likewise, in order for an
argumentation to be a fallacious (to a given group of people) it is necessary and
sufficient for the premises to be not all known to be true (by the group) or
for its chain-of-reasoning to not show (to the group)
that its conclusion is a logical consequence of its premises.
Every fallacious “proof” has faulty
premises or faulty reasoning. Every fallacious “proof” begs-thequestion or begs-the-deduction. Some
argumentations are fallacious for everyone: those with false premises, those
whose conclusions do not follow from their respective premises sets, and those
with other disqualifications.
If the chain-of-reasoning shows that
the conclusion follows but the premises are not all known to be true, then the
argumentation is a deduction but not
a proof. Aristotle said many years ago: “every proof is a deduction but not
every deduction is a proof”. If the premises of a deduction come to be known to
be true, the deduction comes to be a proof. The order does not matter. You can
construct a proof, or demonstration, by securing knowledge of the premises and
then establish that the conclusion follows from them. You can construct a proof
by establishing that the conclusion follows from the premises and then securing
knowledge of them.
In typical cases, some or all of a
demonstration’s premises have been demonstrated. The demonstrations of the
premises may be thought of as added to the demonstration making its extended
demonstration. This process may be continued until we arrive at its fully extended demonstration whose
premises are propositions known to be true by the demonstrator without using
deduction. These ultimate premises of the fully extended deduction may be
called its axioms—regardless of whether they happen to have been adopted
previously as axioms in some axiomatized theory. A
given branch of mathematics may be axiomatized in
various ways, an axiom of one axiomatization being a
deduced theorem of another (Corcoran, 1999a).
Hidden consequence and hidden independence
Two related problem types are central
to logic: consequence problems—discussed above, but not by that name—and
independence problems. Consequence
problems have the form: to show that a given conclusion is a consequence of
a given premise set—if it is. Independence
problems have the form: to show that a given conclusion is not a consequence of a given premise
set—if it is not. Traditionally, a proposition, not a consequence of a set of
propositions, is said to be independent of
the latter, a terminology whose awkwardness needs to be pointed out to students
(Corcoran, 2015, 2010b).
A lengthy deduction that Andrew Wiles discovered shows the Fermat conjecture
to be a consequence of arithmetic axioms. Consequence problems were solved by deduction: deducing the conclusion from
the premises using a series of deductively evident steps. The branch of
mathematical logic that is most relevant to consequence problems is called
proof theory (Corcoran, 1973).
Reinterpreting ‘number’, ‘zero’, and
‘successor’ so as to produce true propositions from the other two axioms and a
false proposition from the Mathematical Induction axiom shows the latter to be
[09] independent of the other two axioms of Gödel’s 1931 axiomatization
of arithmetic. Independence problems were solved by reinterpretation: reinterpreting non-logical constants so as to
produce true premises and false conclusion. There is not time in the first days
to treat independence problems, but they will be dealt with extensively on
later days. The branch of mathematical logic that is most relevant to
independence problems is called model theory (Corcoran, 1973).
A proposition that is a consequence
of (or is independent of) a premise set is said to be a hidden consequence (or a hidden
independence) if it is not obviously such. Without hidden consequence,
deduction would be pointless. Without hidden independence, independence proof
would be pointless. Hidden consequence and hidden independence are basic for
justifying the study of logic and, indeed, for justifying the existence of
logic as a field. This points to another human need
that logic was developed to satisfy (Corcoran, 2010b).
Above we noted that logic was
developed by human beings in response to human needs. One need that initiated
logic was probably the need to be able to distinguish (genuine) proofs from bogus “proofs”: to
distinguish cogent argumentations
from fallacious argumentations. But,
the pursuit of this goal reveals the need to determine of a given conclusion
whether it follows from given premises. Without hidden consequence and hidden
independence no such need would ever arise.
Appendix
Applying
Logical Terminology in History
There are many propositions about
right triangles. Your students probably know that (1) the square on one side of
a right triangle is equal to the sum of the squares on the other two sides.
This follows from the Pythagorean Theorem, as is easily seen. It is also a fact
that (2) the square on one side of a right triangle is equal to the difference
between the squares on the other two sides. This is related to the fact that,
given any three quantities, if the first is the sum of others, then the second
is equal to the difference between the first and the third and, of course, also
the third is equal to the difference between the first and the second. It is
also a fact that (3) the square on any one side of a right triangle not equal
to the sum of the squares on the other two sides is equal to the difference
between those two squares. It is also a fact that (4) the square on any one
side of a right triangle not equal to the difference between the squares on the
other two sides is equal to sum of those two squares.
If Pythagoras proved any one of these
four propositions, he did so by deducing it from propositions he knew to be
true. If he deduced it from propositions he did not know to be true, he did not
have a proof: he had a question-begging deduction—he begged-the-question.
It is not necessary to know that the
last two of the four propositions, (3) and (4) are both true in order to know
that each implies the other. If Pythagoras knew that one implies the other, he
deduced one from the other.
N. Bourbaki,
the legendary mathematician, was not far from the above view when he wrote the
following (Corcoran, 1973: 23):
By a proof, I understand a section of
a mathematical text [...]. Proofs, however, had to exist before the structure
of a proof could be logically analyzed; and this analysis [...] must have
rested [...] on a large body of mathematical writings. In other words, logic,
so far as we mathematicians are concerned, is no more and no less than the
grammar of the language which we use, a language which had to exist before the
grammar could be constructed [...]. The primary task of the logician is thus
the analysis of the body of mathematical texts.... (Bourbaki, 1949).
Acknowledgements
This paper is a revised and expanded
version of a previous paper that was translated into Spanish.
Corcoran, John. (2010). Los primeros días de todo curso de
Lógica. Ergo. Revista de Filosofía de la
Universidad Veracruzana. 25, 31–45. Spanish translation by Patricia Diaz-Herrera.
[10]
The previous paper originated as a handout
for the first day of the fall 2007 version of my graduate course Introduction to Logic for Advanced Students.
Former students in that course, especially Paul Penner
and Patricia Diaz-Herrera, deserve much credit for their contributions. Penner spent long hours ferreting out errors, omissions,
and places that needed work.
The existence of the paper is due
almost exclusively to Diaz-Herrera’s initiative and dedication. Making the
paper from the handout was her idea. And she undertook the translation. I am
very grateful to her.
For encouraging responses, useful
suggestions, and critical insights, my warm thanks to the following: J.
Baldwin, G. Boger, G. Burda,
Jos. Corcoran, M. Cowen, P. Crivelli, T. Drucker, C. Ende, L. Estrada, I. Hamid, F. Hansen, J. Henderson, L. Jacuzzo,
J. Keller, J. Kreiss, J. Legault,
R. Lewin, Y. Liu, R. Main, D. Marans,
C. Martínez-Vidal, H. Masoud, K. Miettinen,
J. Miller, M. Mulhern, F. Nabrasa,
P. Penner, S. Pererê, D. Plache, M. Rind, G. Rising, A. Schremmer,
T. Sullivan, C. Ullman, R. Weaver, L. Woomer, S. Ziewacz, and others.
M. Cerezo,
L. Estrada, M. Mulhern, R. Lewin,
J. M. Sagüillo, A. Zela,
and others were consulted on the translation.
[11]
References
Bourbaki, N. (1949). Foundations of Mathematics for the Working Mathematician. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 14(1), 1-8.
Corcoran, J. (1973). “Gaps between logical theory and mathematical practice”. In
M. Bunge (ed.).
Methodological Unity of Science (pp. 23–50). Dordrecht: Reidel.
Corcoran, J. (1979). Review of “Hintikka, J. and U. Remes. The Method of Analysis”. Mathematical Reviews, 58, 3202.
Corcoran, J. (1989a). Argumentations and logic. Argumentation, 3, 17–43.
Corcoran, J. (1989b). Inseparability of Logic and Ethics. Free Inquiry, Spring, 37–40.
Corcoran, J. (1995). Semantic
Arithmetic: a Preface. Agora, 14,
149–156.
Corcoran, J. (1996). “Information-theoretic logic”. In C.
Martínez et al. (eds.).
Truth in Perspective (pp. 143–176), Aldershot, UK: Ashgate,
Corcoran, J. (1999a). Axiomatic method. Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Corcoran, J. (1999b). Critical thinking and pedagogical license. Manuscrito, 22, 109–16.
Corcoran, J. (2005). Counterexamples and proexamples. Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 11, 460.
Corcoran, J. (2006a). An Essay on Knowledge and Belief. The International Journal of Decision Ethics, 2(2), 125-144.
Corcoran, J. (2006b). C. I. Lewis:
History and Philosophy of Logic. Transactions of the C. S. Peirce Society. 42, 1–9.
Corcoran, J. (2007a).
“A priori/a posteriori”. In J. Lachs
& R. Talisse (eds.). Encyclopedia of American
Philosophy. New York: Routledge.
Corcoran, J. (2007b). “Knowledge and Belief”.
In J. Lachs & R. Talisse
(eds.). Encyclopedia of American Philosophy. New York: Routledge.
Corcoran, J. (2009a). Ambiguity:
lexical and structural. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 15,
235–6.
Corcoran, J. (2009b). Aristotle’s Demonstrative Logic. History and Philosophy of Logic, 30,
1–20.
Corcoran, J. (2009c). “Sentence, proposition, judgment, statement, and fact”. In
W. Carnielli et
al. (eds.) The Many Sides of Logic (pp.
71–103). London, College Publications.
Corcoran, J. (2010a). Essay-Review of “Striker, G., trans. 2009. Aristotle’s Prior Analytics: Book I.
Trans. with Intro. and Comm. Oxford: Oxford University
Press. 2005”. Notre Dame Philosophical
Reviews.
Corcoran, J. (2010b). Hidden
consequence and hidden independence. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 16, 443.
Corcoran, J. (2010c).
Los primeros días de todo curso de Lógica. Ergo.
Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad Veracruzana, 25, 31–45. (Spanish translation by Patricia Diaz-Herrera of a previous version of this paper).
Corcoran, J. (2015). Teaching independence. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 21, 101–102.
Corcoran, J. (2016). Logic teaching in the 21st century. Quadripartita Ratio: Revista de Argumentación y
Retórica, 1(1), 1–34.
Corcoran, J. (2017). Review of “Paseau, Alexander, ‘Knowledge of mathematics without
proof’, British J. Philos. Sci. 66
(2015), no. 4, 775–799”. Mathematical
Reviews.
Corcoran, J., & W.
Frank (2013). Cosmic Justice Hypotheses. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 19, 253.
Corcoran, J., & W.
Frank.
(2015). Assumptions: illative and typographical. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 21, 364–5.
Corcoran, J., W. Frank
& M. Maloney (1974). String theory. Journal of Symbolic Logic,
39, 625–637.
Corcoran, J., &
I. S. Hamid (2014). Objectivity-subjectivity distinctions. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 20,
248.
Corcoran, J., &
I. S. Hamid (2015). Investigating knowledge and opinion. In A. Buchsbaum
& A. Koslow (eds.). The Road to Universal
Logic. Vol. I (pp. 95-126). Basel:
Springer.
[1] Nota del director de Quadripartita ratio: Como el autor lo menciona en la sección de agradecimientos (ver al
final del artículo), la traducción al español de una primera versión de este
artículo fue publicada en 2010 en la revista Ergo de la Facultad de Filosofía de la Universidad Veracruzana (Ergo. Nueva Época, 25, 31-45. ISSN:
0187-6309), bajo la dirección de Ariel Campirán. Esta
nueva versión, que aparece en su idioma original, incluye adiciones y
precisiones importantes, tanto en cantidad como en contenido, y es por tal
motivo que nos pareció pertinente ofrecerla a los lectores de Quadripartita Ratio. Siendo Corcoran un investigador de primer orden en el área de la
lógica, pero también un docente crítico y comprometido, consideramos
fundamental poner este artículo a la disposición de las personas interesadas
para que puedan constatar las diferencias entre las dos versiones y evaluar por
sí mismas su importancia. Y aprovechamos, desde luego, esta nota para agradecer
a nuestros amigos de Ergo por la
amable autorización para la publicación del material ya aparecido en el número
mencionado.