Logic teaching in the 21st century
La enseñanza de la lógica en el siglo 21
John
Corcoran
corcoran@buffalo.edu
Philosophy,
University at Buffalo
Buffalo, NY 14260-4150, USA
Fecha de
recepción: 15-10-15
Fecha
de aceptación: 22-01-16
Corcoran, J. (2016). Logic teaching
in the 21st century.
Quadripartita Ratio: Revista de Retórica y Argumentación, 1(1), 2-31. ISSN: 2448-6485
[02]
Resumen: En la actualidad, estamos mucho mejor preparados para dejar que los
hechos se revelen ellos mismos a nosotros, en vez de ignorarlos o intentar
obstinadamente hacerlos entrar en moldes preconcebidos. Ya dejamos de sentirnos
incómodos ante nuestros estudiantes insistiendo, por ejemplo, que “algunos X
son Y” significa lo mismo que “algún X es Y” y añadiendo, sin gran convicción,
la frase “para los fines de la lógica” cuando encontramos resistencia.
La enseñanza de la
lógica en este siglo puede explotar el nuevo espíritu de objetividad, humildad,
claridad, observacionalismo, contextualismo,
tolerancia y pluralismo. En consecuencia, la enseñanza de la lógica en este
siglo puede acelerar el declive o, al menos, frenar la expansión del espíritu
recurrente de subjetividad, intolerancia, ofuscamiento y relativismo.
Además de este nuevo espíritu, ha
habido en la lógica, en su historia y en la filosofía avances significativos
que podrían mejorar radicalmente la enseñanza de la lógica. Un ejemplo más bien
notable es el hecho de que el proceso de refinamiento de la terminología lógica
ha sido productivo. Los futuros estudiantes de lógica dejarán ya de ser
agobiados por el lastre de una terminología oscura y podrán ser capaces de
leer, pensar, hablar y escribir sobre lógica de una manera más cuidadosa y
gratificante.
Estrechamente
relacionado con esto último se encuentra el uso y el estudio crecientes del
lenguaje natural enriquecido con variables como, por ejemplo: “Toda proposición
x que implica alguna proposición y que es falsa implica también alguna
proposición z que es verdadadera”.
Otro desarrollo positivo
es la culminación del lento rechazo del logicismo. El profesor ya no se siente
impedido de hacer uso de ejemplos de la aritmética y el álgebra, temiendo estar
adoctrinando a los estudiantes con la idea de que toda verdad matemática es una
tautología y que toda falsedad matemática es una contradicción.
Un desarrollo positivo
más es la separación de las leyes de la lógica y de las llamadas verdades
lógicas, esto es las tautologías. Actualmente podemos enseñar la independencia
lógica de las leyes de tercero excluso y no contradicción sin temer que los
estudiantes hayan sido adoctrinados con la idea de que toda ley de la lógica es
una tautología y que toda falsedad lógica es una contradicción. Esta separación
permite al profesor de lógica aplicar la lógica en la clarificación de las
leyes de la lógica.
Este
texto explora los puntos mencionados, los cuales aplican por igual en cursos de
primero, segundo y tercer nivel, esto es “pensamiento crítico”, “lógica
deductiva” y “lógica simbólica”.
Palabras clave:
enseñanza de la lógica, pluralismo, terminología lógica, proposiciones
matemáticas, proposiciones lógicas.
[03]
Abstract: Today we are much better
equipped to let the facts reveal themselves to us instead of blinding ourselves
to them or stubbornly trying to force them into preconceived molds. We no
longer embarrass ourselves in front of our students, for example, by insisting
that “Some Xs are Y” means the same as “Some X is Y”, and lamely adding “for
purposes of logic” whenever there is pushback.
Logic teaching
in this century can exploit the new spirit of objectivity, humility, clarity, observationalism, contextualism,
tolerance, and pluralism. Accordingly, logic teaching in this century can
hasten the decline or at least slow the growth of the recurring spirit of
subjectivity, intolerance, obfuscation, and relativism.
Besides
the new spirit there have been quiet developments in logic and its history and
philosophy that could radically improve logic teaching. One rather conspicuous
example is that the process of refining logical terminology has been
productive. Future logic students will no longer be burdened by obscure
terminology and they will be able to read, think, talk, and write about logic
in a more careful and more rewarding manner.
Closely related
is increased use and study of variable-enhanced natural language as in “Every
proposition x that implies some
proposition y that is false also
implies some proposition z that is
true”.
Another welcome
development is the culmination of the slow demise of logicism.
No longer is the teacher blocked from using examples from arithmetic and
algebra fearing that the students had been indoctrinated into thinking that
every mathematical truth was a tautology and that every mathematical falsehood
was a contradiction.
A further
welcome development is the separation of laws of logic from so-called logical
truths, i.e., tautologies. Now we can teach the logical independence of the
laws of excluded middle and non-contradiction without fear that students had
been indoctrinated into thinking that every logical law was a tautology and
that every falsehood of logic was a contradiction. This separation permits the
logic teacher to apply logic in the clarification of laws of logic.
This lecture expands
the above points, which apply equally well in first, second, and third courses,
i.e. in “critical thinking”, “deductive logic”, and “symbolic logic”.
Keywords:
logic teaching, pluralism, logical terminology, mathematical propositions,
logical proposition.
Logical thinking in mathematics
can be learned only by observation and experience. In fact, the ability to
reason correctly and to understand correct reasoning is itself a prerequisite
to the study of formal logic.
—Solomon
Feferman, The Number Systems.
1964.
Introduction
The
plan of this lecture is to expand each of the six themes contained in the
abstract, each with its own section. Each such thematic section begins with a
quote from the abstract. Within each of
the thematic sections, connections will be made to the other sections and to
the references. None of the sections are definitive: all raise more issues than
they settle. This is in keeping with the new spirit treated in the next section
below. Logic teachers in the 21st century no longer have to pretend that logic
is a completed monolith or seamless tapestry of established truths—or even that
it is moving toward being such. New knowledge reveals new awareness of old
ignorance. New knowledge also begs many questions. Can this result be improved?
How can this result be applied? And many more. The
goals of logic study are not limited to acquisition of truths but include
acquisition of expertise (“Investigating knowledge and opinion”, Corcoran-Hamid,
2015).
Moreover,
logic teachers do not need to pretend to be inculcating truths or even to be
telling the truth to their students. My 1999 essay “Critical thinking and
pedagogical license”, written to be read by students of logic, makes it clear
that there is room in logic teaching for telling untruths and for letting the
students in on the fact that effective teaching requires deviation from fact.
Like
other sciences, there are five distinct kinds of knowledge in logic to be
shared with students - not imparted to them: objectual,
operational, propositional, hypothetical, and expert. Briefly, [04] objectual knowledge is of
objects in the broad sense including individuals, concepts, processes, etc.
Operational knowledge, or know-how, includes ability to observe, judge, deduce,
etc. Propositional knowledge, or know-what, is knowing
a proposition to be true or to be false. The expression hypothetical knowledge may be new to some. In the sense used here,
I define hypothetical knowledge as
knowledge of the “openness” of unsettled propositions and unsolved problems.
Paradoxically put, hypothetical knowledge is knowledge of what is not
knowledge, knowing where the uncharted territory is: for example, knowing of
words whose meanings are not clear, knowing of propositions not known to be
true or false, knowing of arguments not know to be
valid or invalid, the list goes on and on.
This
definition connects with using the noun hypothesis
for “proposition not known to be true and not known to be false”: we have no
other word for this important concept. Although every proposition is either
true or false, not every proposition is either known to be true or known to be
false. Using this terminology, every proposition is either known to be true,
known to be false, or a hypothesis.
Experts
are valued for sharing their “ignorance”—which is a paradoxical way of saying
that they are valued for revealing what they don’t know— their hypothetical knowledge. In fact, experts are
often valued as much for revealing what they don’t know as for revealing what they do know—their propositional knowledge (Corcoran-Hamid,
2015).
Expertise,
the fifth kind of knowledge, includes the practical and theoretical experience
acquired over years of engagement with a discipline’s reality. It includes the
expert’s feel for the subject and the expert’s engagement with the reality the
subject is about. Moreover it unifies and inter-relates the other four kinds of
knowledge. The expert’s hypothetical knowledge is one of the fuels that keep a
discipline alive and growing.
The
recognition of the variety of kinds of knowledge alerts students of what they
have and what they are gaining; it also alerts them of what they might be
missing and what their textbooks might be missing. In earlier times, only two
of these five were explicitly recognized and even then not to the extent
recognized today. For example, Galen recognized only a kind of objectual knowledge—of “universals” such as “human”, “dog”,
and “olive”—and propositional knowledge—such as that the sun is hot (Galen 200?
/1964: 31f, 55f). Over a millennium later, William of Ockham was in the same
rut (William of Ockham 1330?/1990: 18ff). Overtones of
this epistemic dichotomy can be found today, for example, in the dichotomy of
“primitive notions” and “primitive sentences” in Tarski
1941/1995 and in Tarski repeated juxtaposition of
definability with provability. Today we recognize much more. For example, the
capacity to generate sentences is a kind of operational knowledge and the
knowledge of “primitive rules” is in a way objectual
and in a way operational.
§1.
Objectivity and pluralism
Of that which receives precise
formulation in mathematical logic, an important part is already vaguely present
as a basic ingredient of daily discourse. The passage from non-mathematical,
non-philosophical common sense to the first technicalities of mathematical
logic is thus but a step, quickly taken. Once within the field, moreover, one
need not travel to its farther end to reach a frontier; the field is itself a frontier,
and investigators are active over much of its length. Even within an
introductory exposition there is room for novelties which may not be devoid of
interest to the specialis1.
—Quine 1940, Preface.
Today we are
much better equipped to let the facts reveal themselves to us instead of
blinding ourselves to them or stubbornly trying to force them into preconceived
molds. We no longer embarrass ourselves in front of our students, for example,
by insisting that ‘Some Xs are Y’ means the same as ‘Some X is Y’, and lamely
adding “for purposes of logic” when there is pushback.
Logic teaching in this century can
exploit the new spirit of objectivity, [05]
humility, clarity, observationalism, contextualism, tolerance, and pluralism. Accordingly, logic
teaching in this century can hasten the decline or at least slow the growth of
the recurring spirit of subjectivity, intolerance, obfuscation, and relativism.
Wishful
thinking, a close friend of laziness and a sworn enemy of objectivity, has
played such an embarrassing role in the history of logic that many of us cringe
at the mere hint of its appearance. The transition from the feeling “it would
be nice if all Xs were Ys” to the belief “certainly all Xs are Ys” is so easy
it sometimes feels like an implication. And when it becomes too obvious that
not all Xs are Ys, then is the time to drag out “certainly all Xs are reducible
to Ys” or “certainly all Xs are transformable into Ys” or “Xs may be regarded
as Ys”. Rarely is the point made that when we are told explicitly that Xs may
be regarded as Ys, there is at least the suggestion—if not a tacit
admission—that Xs are not Ys.
By
the way, to see that ‘Some Xs are Y’ does not mean the same as ‘Some X is Y’,
one may notice that “Some prime numbers are even” is false: 2 is the only prime
number that is even: no two prime numbers are even. But, “Some prime number is
even” is true: the proexample is 2. (See Corcoran
2005: “Counterexamples and Proexamples”). To be
explicit, “Some prime numbers are even” amounts to “Two or more prime numbers
are even”. Although in general ‘some’ with a singular amounts to ‘at least
one’, nevertheless with a plural it amounts to ‘two or more’: the meaning of
‘some’ is context dependent. There are many other examples. From set theory we
have the truth “Some set is empty” juxtaposed with the falsehood “Some sets are
empty”. Many otherwise excellent texts overlook this point. (See
Cohen-Nagel 1934/1993: 42ff.)
We
no longer regard, for example, ‘Every X is Y”—where ‘Y’ must stand for an
adjective and ‘is’ indicates predication—as interchangeable with ‘Every X is a
Y”—where ‘Y’ must stand for a noun and ‘is’ indicates identity. Russell, Parry,
Smiley, and others all arrived at the same conclusion. (See Corcoran 2008a:
“Aristotle’s many-sorted logic”)
And
we no longer pretend that the two-word expression ‘is a’ before a common noun expresses the membership
relation and that the common noun
following is really a proper name of
a class. See my 2013 “Errors in Tarski’s 1983
truth-definition paper”. The is of
identity can make a predicate out of a proper
name as in ‘two plus one is three’, where ‘two plus one’ is the subject and
‘is three’ the predicate. The is of
predication can make a predicate out of an adjective as in ‘two plus one is
odd’ where ‘two plus one’ is the subject and
‘is odd’ the predicate. A verb phrase for membership—such as ‘belongs
to’ or ‘is a member of’ resembles the is
of identity in that it can make a predicate out of a proper name as in ‘two
plus one belongs to the class of odd numbers’ where ‘two plus one’ is the
subject and ‘belongs to the class of odd numbers’ the predicate. But the proper
name must be a name of a class.
We
no longer try to “reduce” one of these three to one of the other two. The
question of what if anything one of these has in common with either of the
other two we leave to future logicians; the teacher need not pretend to know
the last word.
We
no longer call the adverb ‘not’ a conjunction or a connective, and we don’t
force it to mean “non” or “it is not the case that”
or, even worse, “it is false that”. Of course there are cases where ‘not’ is
naturally interchangeable with ‘it is not that’ and ‘it is not the case that’:
in front of ‘every’ as in ‘not every prime number is odd’. But such situations
are rare: ‘not some integer is divisible by zero’ is ungrammatical but ‘no
integer is divisible by zero’ is true, of course.
We
no longer say that the word ‘nothing’ is a name of the null set, or worse, a
name of the number zero. We no longer use ‘equals’ to mean “is”: (2 + 3) is 5;
there is only one integer between 4 and 6— call it ‘(2 + 3)’, call it ‘5’, or
call it by one of its other names. (See Corcoran-Ramnauth
2013: “Equality and identity”). Using ‘equals’ for ‘is’ in arithmetic may be a
vestige of a time when people thought that (2 + 3) wasn’t 5 itself, but only an
equal of 5. And that mistake may have been reinforced by failing to make the
use-mention distinction: the seven-character name ‘(2 + 3)’ isn’t the
one-character name ‘5’, but they name the same number—which some people might
regard as a kind of equality. Tarski [06] discusses
these mistakes in 1941/1995. When ‘=’ is used for identity as opposed to
equality, it would be better to call it the is sign and
not the equals sign. We try to avoid
expressions that encourage or even tolerate distorted views of the logical
structure of language and we encourage our students to point out such
expressions.
The
string ‘(2 + 3)’ has seven-characters: two parentheses, two digits, one plus
sign, and two spaces. See the 1974 “String Theory” and the 2006 “Schemata”.
If
the logic you know exhausts all logic, your work learning logic is finished.
And if you believe that the logic you know exhausts all logic, why should you
look for places it doesn’t work? After all, you are sure there are none. And
when doubts creep in, apologetics and rationalization come to the rescue; and
if you are desperate, invoking famous authorities might help.
My
primary goal in logic teaching is to connect the students to the reality logic
is about, not to indoctrinate the students in the opinions of famous logicians
or to drill them in the currently fashionable manipulations. The aim is to
bring out the student’s native ability to make autonomous judgments and perhaps
correct or even overthrow the current paradigms—not to swell the ranks of
orthodoxy. Even worse than the enthusiastic orthodox logicians are those who
lack a sense of logical reality and who therefore treat logic like fiction,
spinning out one new artificial system after the other, all equally empty.
What
do I mean by logical reality? What do I mean by physical reality? What do I
mean by mathematical reality? What do I mean by reality? A “formal definition”
is out of the question, but helpful things can be said. In keeping with normal
usage, reality is what a person refers to in making an objective judgment.
There are as many aspects to logical reality as there are categories of logical
judgments. (See Corcoran 2009: “Sentence, proposition, judgment, statement,
fact”). I asked Frango Nabrasa
how he explains reality to people uncomfortable about the word ‘reality’. His
answer: “Reality is what people agree about when they actually agree and what
people disagree about when they actually disagree”. For uses
of the word ‘reality’ in a logical context see, e.g., Russell’s Introduction to (Wittgenstein 1922).
How
is the reality that logic studies accessed? The short answer is “through its
applications”. A longer answer can be inferred from my 1973 article “Gaps
between logical theory and mathematical practice”.
The
applications of logic are to living sciences, technologies, humanities, and
disciplines—a point emphasized by Tarski, Henkin, and others in the Berkeley Logic and Methodology
Group. Before any logic is discussed in the classroom some content should be
presented, preferably content already familiar to the student or, if not
familiar, useful and easily grasped. I have in mind arithmetic, algebra (or
analysis), geometry, set theory, class theory, string theory (syntactics), zoology, botany, and— perhaps
paradoxically—logic itself.
In
particular, before a symbolic argument schema is presented, a discipline or
disciplines and concrete arguments instantiating that schema should be
presented. Of the various ways of presenting an argument perhaps the one least
open to misinterpretation is the premises-line-conclusion
format which consists in listing the premises followed by a line followed
by the conclusion. There is no justification, other than mindless adherence to
tradition, for using an inferential adverb such as ‘therefore’, ‘hence’, ‘so’,
or the triple-dot therefore sign ‘∴’
to mark the conclusion in a presentation of an argument. This confuses the mere
presentation of an argument for consideration with the statement of its
validity. We need to present arguments without seeming to claim their validity.
Actually, use of an inferential adverb is even worse than that: besides
claiming that the conclusion follows it seems to claim the truth of the
premises. See my 1973 “Meanings of implication”, which has been translated into
Spanish.
Here
is what I mean: concrete arguments from arithmetic, geometry, set theory, and
logic are presented first and then some related schemata are given. (see Corcoran 2006: “Schemata”). Incidentally, in [07] this
paper it looked nicer to underline the last premise before the conclusion than
to make a line after the last premise. This will not work for zero-premise
arguments. Another device that is handy is to prefix the conclusion with a
special character having inferential connotations, for example, a question
mark.
Every
number divides itself.
Every
even number divides itself.
Every
triangle resembles itself.
Every
equilateral triangle resembles itself.
Every
set contains itself.
Every
finite set contains itself.
Every
proposition implies itself.
Every
false proposition implies itself.
For
future reference below, note that the above four arguments are in the same
form. It will be important to remind ourselves of one of the ways an argument
can be used as a template for generating the others. This method will be
form-preserving: it generates from one argument new arguments having the same
form. The simplest form-preserving transformation is the operation of substituting
one new non-logical term for every occurrence of a given non-logical term. By
‘new’ here is meant “not already occurring in the argument operated on” and, of
course, the semantic category of the new term must be the same as the one it
replaces. For example, “number” can replace “integer” but it cannot replace
“one”, “even”, “divides”, “square-root”, “plus”, etc.
The
operation just described is called one-new-term-substitution.
Every argument obtained from a given argument by a finite sequence of one-new-term
substitutions is in the same logical form as the given argument. And
conversely, every argument in the same logical form as a given argument is
obtained from the given argument by a finite sequence of one-new-term
substitutions—as long as the given argument involves only finitely many
non-logical terms.
Extending
this result to the case of arguments involving infinitely many non-logical
terms is a mere technicality. Some people will want to take the above as a
formal, “official”, definition of the relation of “being-in-the-same-form-as”.
Compare with Corcoran (1989, “Argumentations and logic”: 27ff).
Such
concrete, material arguments should precede abstract, formal schemas, or
schemata, such as the following.
Every
N Rs itself.
Every
A N Rs itself.
Every
N x is such that xRx.
Every
N x is such that if x is A, then xRx.
P
Q
Presenting
argument schemas in the absence of their concrete instances alienates students
from their native logical intuitions and gives them a distorted sense of logic.
It has led to misconceptions such as that the primary subject matter of logic
is logical forms or even schemata. It has even led to the view that logical
reality excludes concrete arguments. It is also a mistake to call argument
schemas by the expression schematic
arguments: they are schemas and not arguments. Presenting argument schemas
in the presence of their concrete instances is one of the practices I advocate
under the rubric “contextualization”. The same sentiment is in the 1981 Preface to Quine
(1940):
I
used no schemata but referred only to their instances, the actual sentences,
[…]. I did not settle for open sentences, with free variables, but insisted on
closed sentences, true and false. My reason was that these are what logic is
for; schemata and even open sentences are technical aids along the way. (Quine 1940/1981, Preface iv).
Along
with schemata and open sentences to be classified as “technical aids”, Quine would have added logical forms if he had thought of
it. To be [08] perfectly clear, I go a little further and say that I think
teaching propositional logic first is a disservice to the students. Time has
come to refute the myths that propositional logic is “primary”, that it is
presupposed by all other logics, and that it deserves some sort of exalted
status. I do not teach propositional logic as a separate logic but as integral
to basic logic. (Corcoran, 2001: “Second-order logic”). Moreover, I do not even
mention “prothetic” or “quantified propositional
logic”—which doesn’t even make sense. See Section 6 below. As a first,
introductory system of logic, I teach identity logic whose only logical
constants are identity and inidentity. (Corcoran-Ziewacz, 1979: “Identity
Logics”). Here are some examples of valid premise-conclusion arguments
in identity logic.
+0
= 0
-0
= 0
+0
= -0
+0
= 0
-0
= 0
-0
= +0
+0
= 0
+0
≠ 1
0
≠ 1
+0
= 0
+0
≠ 1
1
≠ 0
√0
= +0
+0
= -0
-0
= 0
0
= √0
§2.
History and philosophy
Here
and elsewhere we shall not have the best insight into things until we see them
growing from their beginnings.
—Aristotle
Besides
the new spirit there have been quiet developments in logic and its history and
philosophy that could radically improve logic teaching.
Today
more than ever before, we are alert to the human practices that gave rise to
the living discipline we call logic: logic arises first as an attempt to
understand proof or demonstration, alternatively— in a broader setting—to
understand the axiomatic method and its presuppositions. This point of view is
attested in the first paragraph of the book that marks the historical origin of
logic: Aristotle’s Prior Analytics. It
is echoed, amplified, and updated in Cohen and Nagel’s classic Introduction to Logic (Cohen-Nagel,
1934/1993). It is given an authoritatively mathematical restatement in the
first paragraph of what is arguably the most successful and influential modern
logic text: Alfred Tarski’s Introduction to Logic (Tarski,
1941/1995). Alonzo Church’s classic Introduction to Mathematical Logic
(Church, 1956) makes a very closely related point on his first page. Aside from
Galen and Sextus Empiricus,
perhaps, this Aristotelian insight was largely ignored by logicians until
Hilbert, Gödel, and others made it stand out. After World War II, Bourbaki’s support of it was influential. (See Corcoran,
2009: “Aristotle’s Demonstrative Logic”).
As
soon as the study of axiomatic method is undertaken, we slowly become aware
that the same process of logical deduction used to obtain theorems from axioms
is also used to obtain conclusions from arbitrary premises—whether known to be
true or not. Evert Beth called this one of Aristotle’s most important
discoveries even though Aristotle never made the point explicitly, as far as I
know.
Thus
logic becomes a broader field: one whose aims include determining whether a
given conclusion follows from given premises—or, what is the same thing,
determining whether a given premise-conclusion argument is valid. Once this is
undertaken, we see that the premises and conclusions need to be subjected to
logical analysis—and that our methods of determining validity and invalidity
need investigation, and so on.
[09]
The
concern with determining whether a given conclusion follows from given
premises—determining whether a given argument is valid—and the general
methodology for approaching this concern is one of the perennial constants in
logic which gets reconstructed and reaffirmed century after century starting
with Aristotle. I have made this point in different ways in several papers. In
Corcoran-Wood (1980), the very first paragraph reads as follows.
It
is one thing for a given proposition to follow or to not follow from a given
set of propositions and it is quite another thing for it to be shown either that the given proposition
follows or that it does not follow. Using a formal deduction to show that a
conclusion follows and using a countermodel to show that a conclusion does not follow are both traditional practices recognized by
Aristotle and used down through the history of logic. These practices
presuppose, respectively, a criterion of validity and a criterion of invalidity
each of which has been extended and refined by modern logicians: deductions are
studied in formal syntax (proof theory) and countermodels
are studied in formal semantics (model theory).
The
method of countermodels, or counterinterpretations,
which is for establishing invalidity, is a complicated and mathematically
sophisticated form of Aristotle’s method of counterarguments. The countermodel method has string-theoretic and set-theoretic
prerequisites making it unsuited for elementary logic teaching. However, the
counterargument method—used by Aristotle long before set theory or string
theory were discovered—is well suited and, moreover, it lends itself to serving
as an introduction to the method of countermodels.
What
are the differences between the two methods? From a student’s perspective,
roughly speaking, in the method of counterarguments the meanings of the
non-logical expressions are changed by changing
their wordings—examples are given in Section 5 below—whereas in the method of countermodels the meanings of the non-logical expressions
are changed without changing their
wordings: the wordings of the non-logical expressions are fixed but their
meanings are changed—‘reinterpreted’ is a technical term often used. The method
of countermodels requires separation of wordings from
meanings, separating syntax from semantics, which is a prerequisite to the
perplexing idea of reinterpretation of a language.
Admittedly,
a historical perspective in logic teaching has been rare: Tarski,
Church, and Quine notwithstanding. But, if my advice
is followed, it will be increasingly emphasized in 21st century
logic teaching.
Another
related feature of 21st century logic teaching will be contextualizing. For
example, it will not even be sufficient to see logic emerge in Aristotle’s mind
in response to his study of axiomatic method in Plato’s Academy; it will be
necessary to see Aristotle in his historical context: his predecessors and
successors. To do that we could review the series: Thales, Pythagoras,
Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, Euclid, Archimedes, Galen.
§3.
Terminology
The
best notation is no notation; whenever possible, avoid complicated formalisms.
—Paul Halmos
Besides
the new spirit, there have been quiet developments in logic and its history and
philosophy that could radically improve logic teaching. One rather conspicuous
example is that the process of refining logical terminology has been
productive. Future logic students will no longer be burdened by obscure
terminology and they will be able to read, think, talk, and write about logic
in a more careful and more rewarding manner.
The
goal of producing students who confidently and accurately think, speak, and
write about logic is closely connected to the goal of producing students who
can access the reality logic is about and who [10] can make autonomous
judgments on logical issues. These goals are served by developing the ability
to read logical writings—a skill that is not innate. Students must acquire it
for themselves, but a teacher can help. One way a teacher can help students to
acquire this skill is to read aloud to them important passages. As linguists
know, but students often don’t, the mind takes information more directly from
spoken language than from the written. See my 2009 “Sentence, Proposition,
Judgment, Statement, and Fact: Speaking about the Written English Used in
Logic”.
And
do not fail to reread, sometimes two or more readings are needed to get the
meaning to emerge. Also try to get the students to articulate what they
experience. Encourage the students to see not only what the author is saying
but also how the author said it: what choices, compromises, and trade-offs were
made. And never fail to be interested in
the students’ interpretations and whether the students agree with the author’s
decisions.
At
each stage of a logic course some passages will be more appropriate than
others. Boole, De Morgan, Whitehead, Russell, Tarski,
Cohen, Nagel, and Quine all produced models of lucid
and rewarding passages. One of my favorites for beginning students is the
section “Counterexamples and Proexamples” in the 1993
second edition of the classic Cohen-Nagel Introduction
to Logic, page xxv. Other gems are scattered thoughout
this paper.
A
student asked why my list of logical-gem writers started with Boole. I could
have gone back to Ockham, or even Augustine, but there are very few before
that. It took a long time for our predecessors to learn how to write logic.
We
no longer tolerate logicians who think they can escape criticism for confusing
or misleading language by admitting to it in advance; an abuse of language
isn’t corrected by being identified in advance. Logicians don’t earn our
forgiveness by explicitly forgiving themselves. Using ‘expression’, ‘term’,
‘concept’, ‘condition’, and other words interchangeably is not conducive to
learning. Likewise, ‘sentence’, ‘proposition’, ‘judgment’, ‘statement’,
‘assertion’, ‘claim’, and ‘fact’ all have their proper and separate ranges of
uses. (See Corcoran, 2009: “Sentence, Proposition, Judgment, Statement, and
Fact”).
However
much a teacher may dislike a certain widely-used or traditional logic
expression, that expression must be discussed in class in order for the
students to be able to read the literature. Pretending that the expression
doesn’t exist—or that it is universally regarded by all competent logicians as
a taboo expression—is not serving the student. Moreover, many such expressions
are used differently by different logicians and the student needs to know this.
An apt example is the word ‘proposition’, etymologically parallel to the Greek
word protasis
that Aristotle used for the things that could serve as premises and as
conclusions of arguments. For example, if the word ‘proposition’ is not
discussed with students, they will have trouble figuring out why Quine (1970) would spend so much time and energy trying to
persuade people not to use the word. One useful paper—accessible with some help
to beginning students—is my 2011 “Hare and Others on the Proposition”.
The
use-mention distinction, without which the Tarski
truth-definition paper would have been inconceivable, is essential: ‘10’ is a
numeral, 10 is a number, and ‘10’ denotes ten in Arabic base-ten notation—but
‘10’ denotes two in binary or base-two notation. If use-mention cannot be done
the first day, it should be done in the first week.
As
important as the use-mention distinction is, even more important is the
attitude that gave rise to it: the motivation to pursue logical reality and
accuracy. People who appreciate the use-mention distinction, the logical
analysis underlying it, and the terminology created to use it are also ready to
seek further important distinctions and to seek higher levels of precision in
logical writing. Another similar distinction is the sense-denotation dichotomy
prominent in the writings of modern logicians such as Frege,
Carnap, and Church—but already applied in the first
sentence of Aristotle’s Categories—which
begins his Organon
(Greek for “instrument”), a group of writings containing the first logic book.
Another one is the type-token-occurrence distinction, a trichotomy
that originated [11] in Peirce’s writings and that is essential for clarity in
discussing logic. See my paper on schemata (Corcoran, 2006: sect. 3, especially
228ff).
Any
introduction to the literature of logic must warn students of obstacles such as
inept and useless hijacking of entrenched normal language: logicians have been
known to steal expressions they didn’t need and would have been happier
without. Mistakenly explaining ‘is’ as ‘is identical with’ is one example.
In
normal English, ‘Abe is Ben’ means roughly
“Abe is no-one but Ben”: “Abe and Ben are one and the same person”. Using Tarski’s terminology, the sentence ‘Abe is Ben’ is true if
and only if the name ‘Abe’ denotes the person Ben. To say that Abe and Ben are
alike in relevant respects, ‘Abe is identical to Ben’ would be used. In fact, a
person could say without raising eyebrows ‘Abe is identical to Ben even though
Abe thinks he is superior’. But in logic literature, ‘Abe is identical to Ben’
means that Abe is no-one but Ben, that Abe and Ben are one and the same person—uselessly
employing ‘identical to’. No logician could say ‘Abe is identical to Ben even
though Abe thinks he is superior’: that would be practically a
self-contradiction. Logicians are good at compartmentalizing: speaking English
at home and “Loglish” at work. Aristotle set the
precedent.
A
closely related example is using ‘equals’ where ‘is’ belongs. Once this abuse
of language is established it is awkward to make points such as that every side
of an equilateral triangle equals both of the other two sides neither of which
is the other. (See Corcoran-Ramnauth,
2013r.) It is by no means the case that using ‘equals’ for ‘is’ is
ubiquitous in logic writing. Quine (1940) routinely
used ‘is’ not ‘equals’, where identity is to the point.
No
discussion of terminology would be complete without revealing nearly entrenched
absurdities the students need to be warned of and explicitly excused from. The
teacher must arrange class terminological and typographical conventions so that
writing logic is not unnecessarily tedious. First, the student should be
excused from the convention of italicizing variables instead of leaving them in
roman—as if there were some sacred taboo that would be violated by writing
‘every number x’ in roman instead of ‘every number x’ in italic. This convention eats up a lot of time better spent on
other things. Second, the student should be excused from compulsive use of
quotes. Of course, it is important to make sure use-mention is observed, but
there are other devices that make less clutter and use less time. Third, chose
notation that is easy to read and easy to remember, e.g. for “and” use &
instead of an inverted vee; for “the successor of”
use ess as in y = sx
instead of the accent as in y = x` (read ecks-accent,
not ecks-prime). Under this rule comes minimizing the
number of subscripts, superscripts, font changes, foreign alphabets, etc.
Also,
simplify spelling: write ‘premise’ not ‘premiss’.
By the way, premises rhymes with cannabis, not canopies, and processes rhymes
with auspices, not recipes: if you are ever tempted to be fancy—God
forbid—check your dictionary. As Frango Nabrasa warns, mispluralizing
English nouns as if they were Greek or Latin doesn’t compensate for mispluralizing Greek or Latin nouns as if they were
English. Your logic students trust you to be a model speaker of the language of
instruction. Don’t betray that trust.
§4.
Variable-enhanced language
The
variable ranges over its values but is replaceable by its substituents.
In arithmetic, the variable has numbers such as zero and one as its values but
has numerals such as ‘0’ and ‘1’ as its substituents.
—Frango Nabrasa
Closely
related is increased use and study of variable-enhanced natural language as in
“Every proposition x that implies some proposition y that is false also implies
some proposition z that is true”.
One
variable-enhanced paraphrase of ‘every person follows some person’ is ‘every
person x follows some person y’, but a more explicit paraphrase is ‘every
person x is such that x follows some person y’. The second occurrence of x is a
pronoun [12] occurrence and the first marks the antecedent referent of the pronoun. The second occurrence refers
back to the first. Every variable occurrence in a well-formed variable-enhanced
English sentence is either a pronoun or an antecedent. But not every expression that resembles a sentence
actually is a sentence, either having a truth-value or expressing a proposition
having a truth-value. Consider ‘x follows some person’, where the pronoun lacks
an antecedent referent as in the unenhanced ‘he follows some person’.
Whenever
there is a pronoun without an antecedent, the expression is not a sentence (expressing a proposition), although it could be a predicate (expressing a condition): ‘x follows some person’ expresses
a condition satisfied by every person who follows some person. (See Tarski 1941/1995: sect.1, 5ff).
Every
antecedent-occurrence of a variable is immediately after a common noun—the range-indicator for the variable. The
common noun person is the range-indicator
for the two occurrences of variable x in ‘every person x is such that x follows
some person y’. It is also the range-indicator for the occurrence of the
variable y. But in many sentences there are different range-indicators for the
occurrences of different variables as in ‘every number x is denoted by some
numeral y’ or ‘every number x is the length of some expression y’.
In
many cases, roughly speaking, a range-indicator is to a variable as a common
noun is to a pronoun. Church makes a similar point in Church (1956).
Whenever
there is an antecedent without a pronoun, the expression can be made more
explicit. For example, in the sentence ‘every person x is such that x follows
some person y’, the last variable-occurrence is an antecedent having no pronoun
referring back to it. The sentence can be made more explicit in multiple ways
each having its own uses.
every
person x is such that x follows y for some person y
every
person x is such that, for some person y, x follows y
every
person x is such that some person y is such that, x follows y
for
every person x, some person y is such that x follows y
for
every person x, for some person y, x follows y
It
is even possible to get the pronoun be to its own antecedent.
every
person x follows some person y
Anyway,
there are several reasons for fine-tuning ones native ability to paraphrase
into variable-enhanced language including, first, to understand better the
logical form of the propositions expressed and, second, to prepare to translate
into logically perfect languages, e.g., a symbolic formalized language. See
“Logical form” in the Cambridge
Dictionary of Philosophy, second and third editions.
It
is my opinion that it is often easier to discern logical relations between
propositions when they are expressed in variable-absent language than in fully
explicit variable-enhanced language. However, it is often the case that logical
relations are easier to discern using partly variable-enhanced language than
either unenhanced or fully enhanced. But whatever opinion you may have, I hope
you articulate it carefully and see what its consequences are and what might
explain it.
On
the subject of terminological transparency, whenever variables are introduced,
constants should be introduced and the constant-variable distinction in logic
and pure mathematics should be contrasted with the constant-variable
distinction in science and applied mathematics. In logic and pure mathematics,
constants and variables are symbols with contrasting sorts of meanings. In
science and applied mathematics, constants and variables are not symbols but
things, quantities with contrasting temporal behaviors.
My
weight at this instant is a constant. My weight over this month is a variable.
My age in years is a variable that is constant between birthdays. (See [13] Tarski, 1941/1995: 3).
In the ordinary senses of ‘variable’, there is nothing variable about the
variables in a given interpreted symbolic-language sentence or in a given
variable-enhanced natural-language sentence. Logicians in the 21st century no
longer say that such variables have variable meanings or that they denote
variable things or that they denote ambiguously. Moreover, the fact that there
may be contexts in which a variable is in some natural sense variable has
nothing to do with why they are called variables.
Returning
to the subject of validity, consider the following premise-conclusion
arguments.
every person follows some person
every
person follows some person who follows some person
every person follows some
person
every
person who follows some person follows some person
every person follows some person
every
person follows some person who follows some person who follows some person
every person follows some
person
every
person who follows some person follows some person who follows some person
It
is easy to see that each of these arguments is valid in the sense that its
conclusion follows from its premises, i.e., that the conclusion simply brings
out explicitly information already implicit in the premise—or at least does not
add any information not in the premises—as explained in Corcoran (1998:
“Information-theoretic logic”). Other logicians make similar points using other
words. For example, Cohen and Nagel wrote the following.
The
logical consequences of a proposition are not phenomena which follow it in
time, but are rather parts of its meaning. While our apprehension of premises
sometimes precedes that of their conclusion, it is also true that we often
first think of the conclusion and then find premises which imply it.
On
the next page, they added: “That a proposition has definite logical
consequences even if it is false follows also from the fact that these logical
consequences or implications are part of its meaning”. (Cohen-Nagel,
1934/1993: 9).
At
this point some readers might ask, as one actually did:
Would
you agree with the following? An
argument is logically valid if and only if it takes a form that makes it
impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion nevertheless to be
false.
I
agree that an argument is valid iff every argument in
the same form is valid. See Section 1 above. The ambiguous word ‘form’ is used
in the sense of Corcoran (1989: “Argumentations and logic”), Quine (1970: Philosophy
of logic), and others: every argument has exactly one form. I would also
agree that an argument is valid iff it is logically
impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false.
But
I have some disagreements. First, a minor point of rhetoric: I would not
qualify ‘valid’ with ‘logically’; it would suggest that I recognize other sorts
of validities. This in turn would raise the questions of what they are, what
are the differences among them, and what they all have in common that justifies
calling them validities. I prefer to set that to the side.
My
important disagreement is with the naïve Platonistic
suggestion that abstract logical forms are what make concrete arguments valid, that concrete arguments are valid in virtue of abstract form. I think this
is destructive to clear thinking about logic; it has things backward in an
alienating and oppressive way. A valid argument is made valid by the
containment of its conclusion’s information in its premise-set’s information.
To see whether a concrete argument is valid, students should be encouraged to
understand its propositions and to see whether the conclusion’s information can
be extracted from that of the premises or whether the [14] conclusion’s
information goes beyond that of the premises.
What
can we call the special property of abstract argument forms whose concrete
instances are all valid? We cannot use ‘validity’ because that has been used
for a property of concrete arguments. Calling a form valid would be a confusing
category mistake: it would be ascribing to an abstract object a property
applicable only to concrete objects. To use Peirce’s example, it would be like
saying that a color has a color, e.g. saying that green is green, i.e., that
greenness has greenness, that green has greenness, that greenness is green.
I
define an abstract argument form to be omnivalid if all of its concrete instances are valid; nullovalid if
none are valid. Every argument form is omnivalid or nullovalid, since every two arguments in the same form are
either both valid or both invalid.
I
would add, paraphrasing Cohen-Nagel (1934/1993), that it is not the form that makes the argument
valid; it is having valid instances that makes the form omnivalid:
the form is omnivalid in virtue of its valid
instances; the valid instance is not valid in virtue of its form. Cohen-Nagel
(1934/1993) wrote the following on page 12.
An
argument is valid in virtue of the implication between premises and conclusion
[…] and not in virtue of […] the form which we have abstracted [sc. from it].
This
is a good place to distinguish forms from schemata. (See Corcoran, 2006:
“Schemata”). The instances of a form are all valid or all invalid. But there
are schemata that have both valid instances and invalid instances. All
one-premise arguments, whether valid or invalid, are instances of the following
schema.
P
Q
Every
one-premise argument having a negation for its premise, whether valid or
invalid, is an instance of the following schema.
It
is not the case that P
Q
Every one-premise argument having a negation as its
conclusion, whether valid or invalid, is an instance of the following schema.
P
It is not the case that Q
I define a schema whose instances are all valid to
be panvalid,
whose instances are all invalid paninvalid, and those among whose instances are found both
valid arguments and invalid arguments neutrovalid. (See Cohen-Nagel, 1934/1993,
Editor’s Introduction: xvii-xxxvii, especially xxxi ff).
Needless to say the class of concrete arguments has
no members in common with either the class of forms or the class of schemata.
Moreover, the latter two are also disjoint, i.e. the class of forms has no
member in common with the class of schemata. At this point, I would warn
against thinking of omnivalidity or panvalidity as a kind of validity—as ‘validity’ is used
here and in my other writings.
In this work there is only one kind of validity and
that is predicable only of concrete arguments. In the sense of ‘valid’ used
here it would be an incoherency, a category mistake, to affirm or deny that
something other than concrete arguments is valid. For the differences between
logical forms and schemata see Cohen-Nagel (1934/1993, Editor’s Introduction: xvii-xxxvii, especially xxxi ff). The
distinction between an argument’s unique form and its multiple schemata
corresponds closely to Quine’s distinction between a
sentence’s unique “entire structure” and its other
“structure”, for example, its truth-functional structure. (See
Quine 1970, Philosophy
of Logic: 48f; Also see Tarski-Givant, 1987:
43f).
Returning to the above four arguments that premise
“every person follows some person”, it would be interesting to discuss them and
the infinitude of others constructed using the same transformations: i.e.,
taking a previously constructed [15] relative clause beginning ‘who follows …’
and inserting it after the noun ‘person’.
But before going on we should express in
variable-enhanced language the proposition expressed using the relative clause
attached to the subject in the following.
every person who
follows some person follows some person
every person x who
follows some person y follows some person z
every person x who
follows some person y is such that x follows some person z
every person x who
is such that x follows some person y is then such that x follows some person z
every person x is
such that if x follows some person y, then x follows some person z
every person x is
such that if, for some person y, x follows y, then for some person z, x follows
z
The above relative clauses are all restrictive, so
called because, in typical cases, they restrict the extension of the
noun-phrase they terminate: the extension of ‘person who follows some person’
is typically a proper subset of the extension of ‘person’. Restrictive relative
clauses are never set off by commas.
But, as we learned in grammar class, there are attributive relative
clauses that are always set off by commas and that are never parts of noun
phrases.
every person leads
some person
every person follows some person
every person, who
follows some person, leads some person
every
person leads some person
every
person follows some person
every person, who
leads some person, follows some person
every
person, who leads some person, follows some person
every person follows
some person
every person, who leads some person, follows
some person
every person leads
some person
every person, who leads some person, follows
some person
every person leads
some person and follows some person
The proposition—expressed using the comma—“every
person, who leads some person, follows some person” contains exactly the same
information as “every person leads some person and every person follows some
person”. In contrast, the proposition—expressed without the comma—“every person
who leads some person follows some person” does not even imply “every person
leads some person and follows some person”. In fact, the proposition “every
person who leads some person follows some person” is implied by “every person
follows some person”. But of course, the proposition “every person, who leads
some person, follows some person” is not implied by “every person follows some
person”. For applications of these ideas to Peano and
Gödel, see Sagüillo (1999: Sections 3.1 and 3.2).
There are many pitfalls in variable-enhanced English
and many of those pitfalls are made even more dangerous when the inevitable
sentence-abbreviating occurs. After all, variable-enhanced English isn’t
English and the “intuitions” that are reliable in English often need tweaking,
or amending before being applied to variable-enhanced English. The following
sentences express one and the same proposition: they all arise from
variable-enhancement of the same plain-English sentence.
every
person x follows some person y
every person
y follows some person z
every person z
follows some person x
There are various ways that a tyro can misunderstand
these and conclude not only that they don’t express the same proposition but
that their propositions are logically independent as are the [16] following.
The variables occupy places normally reserved for participles or something that
can replace a participle.
every
person walking follows some person jogging
every
person jogging follows some person running
every person running
follows some person walking
When a batch of variable-enhanced sentences all
involve one and the same common noun, as these all involve only ‘person’, it is
natural to leave the noun “understood”. To read them, the noun must be restored
“by the mind”—to use Tarski’s terminology from his
1941 Introduction.
every x
follows some y
every y
follows some z
every z follows some
x
A person’s “English intuition” feels that the
letters x, y, and z are nouns and the sentences are converted into spoken
English somewhat as follows. [The word ‘whigh’ below
names ‘y’ and rhymes with high, nigh, sigh, thigh, etc.]
every ecks follows some whigh
every whigh follows some zee
every zee follows
some ecks
Misleading the student to think of
variables as common nouns is even more likely when the variables are put into
plural form as in ‘all xs follow some ys’ without an apostrophe or ‘all x’s
follow some y’s’ with an apostrophe—pronounced “all eckses follow some whighs”. There
is another problem with pluralizing a variable using the apostrophe: that form
is already used as a possessive as in ‘if x is even, x’s
successor is odd’. To the best of my knowledge, no English noun pluralizes
using apostrophe-ess.
Closely related to the mistake of treating
variables as common nouns is the mistake of treating common nouns as proper
names of sets. This can happen several ways: one is to write ‘for every x ε
person’ instead of ‘for every person x’; another even worse is to write ‘for
every x, if x ε person’. This is not grammatically correct variable-enhanced
English. Moreover, it creates typographical clutter and it sets a scientistic tone inconsistent with autonomous judgment and
independent thinking. We don’t honor our heroes by mindlessly repeating their
mistakes. In this case, Peano seems to be the
originator of these mistakes (Quine, 1987).
The logic teacher will want to be alert
for students falling into pitfalls. Every time a student falls into a pitfall,
the teacher has an opportunity to instruct the class in the intricacies of
variable-enhanced English and the logical analysis of English.
Logic teaching in the 21st century will
look for opportunities to connect logic with other things the student has
previously learned. For example, in language, composition, rhetoric, classics,
history, and other classes, a student might learn Quintilian’s four fundamental
textual operations: addition, deletion, substitution, and transposition. These
four words represent my interpretation of Quintilian’s meanings not a
translation of his words. Other English words are just as good: insertion,
extraction, replacement, permutation. For operation, transformation would do as
well. The Latin words Quintilian uses are adiectio, detractio, mutatio, and ordinatio.
The terminology is not fixed. Quintilian
(96?/1920) observed that these four operations can be
used to improve the rhetorical effectiveness of sentences (Inst. IX. iii. 27) and that they can be misused to undermine
effectiveness and introduce errors (Inst.
I. v. 8). The Latin words Quadripartita
Ratio in the title of our journal are Quintilian’s alluding
to four transformations.
All four were used in this paper. The
transitions to, from, and among the six variable-enhanced translations of
‘every person follows some person’ illustrate all four of Quintilian’s
transformation types: (1) addition of variables and (2) deletion, (3)
substitution of ‘every person x is such that’ for ‘for every person x’, (4)
transposition of ‘for some person x’. These transitions call to mind the
meaning-preserving transformations in Zellig Harris’s
“discourse analysis” that led via his student Noam Chomsky to [17] modern
transformational grammars. (See Corcoran, 1972: “Harris on
the Structures of Language”).
The first two—under the names lengthening and
shortening (or ellipsis)—are discussed and exemplified in several of my papers,
(e.g. Corcoran, 2003: 266):
Given two sentences expressing one and
the same proposition, often one corresponds more closely to the logical form of
the proposition than the other. Often one reveals more of the logical structure
of the proposition or contains fewer logically irrelevant constituents. Some of
the easiest examples of the grammatical–logical discrepancy are found in the
so-called elliptical sentences that have been shortened for convenience or in
the so-called expletive sentences that have been redundantly lengthened for
emphasis or for some other rhetorical purpose.
Moreover,
logic teaching in the 21st century will look for opportunities to make the
student aware of the fact that logic can enrich the student’s understanding of
all previous learning. Awareness of logical issues can be like a sixth sense
making other senses more vivid.
The issue of the attributive/restrictive
distinctions is an apt example. Let us pause here to review some
attributive/restrictive distinctions and the structural ambiguities requiring
them. In this paper, when ‘concrete’ and ‘abstract’ are used with the common
noun ‘argument’ they are used attributively, but when ‘valid’ and ‘omnivalid’ are used with the same common noun they are used
restrictively. Thus, “Every concrete argument has its abstract form” is
logically equivalent to “Every argument, which is concrete, has its form, which
is abstract”. However, “Every valid argument has its omnivalid
form” is logically equivalent to “Every argument that is valid has its form
that is omnivalid”.
The adjective-noun phrase is
structurally ambiguous. It has ‘attributive’ and ‘restrictive’ uses as
explained in Corcoran (2009: “Ambiguity: Lexical and Structural”).
In some cases, called attributive by
grammarians, the implication is that the adjective applies to everything coming under the noun: “Every
concrete argument has its abstract form” implies “Every argument is concrete”
and “Every form is abstract”. The point of attributive usage is often
rhetorical, pedagogical, and expository: to remind the reader of an adjective
previously applied to everything in the noun’s extension—the extension of
‘concrete argument’ is the same as that of ‘argument’.
In other cases, called restrictive by
grammarians, the implication is not
that the adjective applies to everything coming under the noun: “Every valid
argument has its omnivalid form” does not imply
“Every argument is valid” and it does not imply “Every form is omnivalid”. In fact,
to the contrary, as a matter of conversational implicature
in the Grice sense, it suggests or “implicates” the opposite, i.e. “Not every
argument is valid” and “Not every form is omnivalid”.
(See Grice, 1989: 24ff). The point of restrictive
usage is often qualificational: to restrict the
noun’s extension—the extension of ‘valid argument’ is a proper subset of that
of ‘argument’. See Sagüillo (1999) and Corcoran
(2009: “Ambiguity: Lexical and Structural”).
As said above it is important to note,
however, that although in this paper,
whenever ‘concrete’ and ‘abstract’ are
used with the common noun ‘argument’, they are used attributively, other works
differ. That said, nevertheless, in this and every other work I can think of,
whenever ‘concrete’ and ‘abstract’ are used with very general common nouns such
as ‘object’, ‘entity’, ‘individual’, ‘substance’, etc., they are used
restrictively. In fact, some writers seem to think that abstract objects and
concrete objects are mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive of reality.
Some older logic texts used the words explicative and determinative for occurrences of adjectives closely related to
those called attributive and restrictive above. Roughly, whereas attributive and restrictive concern the structure of the proposition, explicative and determinative concern the structure of the reality being
discussed—in the case of a true proposition, the structure of the fact. (See
Watts, 1725/1790, Logick:
Part II, ch. II, sect V).
The topic of structural ambiguity—also
called amphiboly and amphibology—is a rich one whose [18] surface was hardly
scratched above. In fact, there are many more things to teach and to learn
about the structural ambiguity of the adjective-noun construction: every
individual student is a student and, conversely, every student is an individual
student. This example and those above bring to mind one of the most
embarrassing chapters in the history of logic: the one titled “The law of inverse
variation of intension and extension”. (See Cohen-Nagel
1934/1993: 33).
Above I said that logic teaching in the 21st century
will look for opportunities to connect logic with other things the student has
previously learned. This section (§ 4) alone gives evidence of logic’s
relevance and applicability to grammar, rhetoric, and argumentation.
§5.
Mathematical propositions, arguments, deductions, and counterarguments
Since
x + 2 = 2 + x for any number x, it is
true for some number x. Thus, as used
here, any implies some and some does not exclude any.
—Whitehead (1911/1948: 8)
Another
welcome development is the culmination of the slow demise of logicism. No longer is the teacher blocked from using
examples from arithmetic and algebra fearing that the students had been
indoctrinated into thinking that every mathematical truth was a tautology and
that every mathematical falsehood was a contradiction.
Our students already know some elementary
mathematics. Logic teaching in the 21st century can follow Tarski’s
lead—in his Introduction to Logic (Tarski, 1941/1995)—by building on that knowledge, extending
it, and using extensions of it to illustrate logical principles and methods. It
is an insult to our students to teach as if a little elementary mathematics is
beyond their abilities or worse that warm and fuzzy examples will appeal to
them. Our students already know the laws of commutativity
and associativity of addition of integers in forms
such as the following taken from elementary textbooks (Tarski
1941/1995: sect. 3).
C1: Commutativity:
x + y = y + x
A1: Associativity:
(x + (y + z)) = ((x + y)
+ z)
There are so many useful, important, and enriching
things to say in a logic course about these laws of arithmetic it is hard to
choose where to start. The first thing to do perhaps is to expand these
highly-compressed elliptical sentences into variable-enhanced natural language.
Tarski emphasizes that natural languages can express
anything expressible in a formalized language and that there are many
pedagogical advantages in translating a formula into natural language. In fact,
in many passages he seemed to say that formalisms were abbreviations of
colloquialisms.
C2: Where x and y are integers, x plus y is y plus x.
Since the initial sentence C1 has no singular/
plural feature and since standard first-order sentences are generally
translated using the singular grammatical “number”, it is worth exploring a
singular form.
C3: Where x is an
integer, where y is an integer, x plus y is y plus x.
Do
C2 and C3 express the same proposition as C1? Do C2 and C3 express the same
proposition? Do C2 and C3 have the same consequences?
Is
there any connection between the contrast of C2 with C3 and the contrast between
the two-place quantifier ∀xy
and the one-place quantifier repeated ∀x∀y
as in Tarski (1941/1995)?
The
students will notice that the sentence C3 is very close to the sentence C4
below, where the second quantification comes at the end. They will also notice
(1) that C4 is a little more natural and (2) that it exemplifies the fact that
in variable-enhanced [19] language the quantifications often follow the
variable-occurrences they bind.
C4: Where x is an
integer, x plus y is y plus x, where y is an integer.
Asking the students why formalized
language differs from natural language in quantification location alerts them
to the phenomenon and at the same time extends the range of sentences they are
comfortable symbolizing.
The propositions expressed by singular forms of the commutativity law clearly apply in the case of a single
number that has two or more names: e.g., zero is named ‘+0’ and ‘-0’. Thus, the
students have no problem deducing ‘(+0 + -0) = (-0 + +0)’ from C1, C3, or C4.
In fact, to be clear, the following are both valid.
Where x is an integer, where y is an integer, x plus y is y plus x.
Where x is an integer,
where y is the same integer, x plus y is y plus x.
Where x is an integer, where y is an integer, x plus y is y plus x.
Where x is an integer,
where y is a different integer, x plus y is y plus x.
When conversing with beginners it is important to
recognize and validate their insights. For example, some will notice that there
is nothing to the premise of these two arguments besides the conclusions, i.e.,
the two conclusions together imply the premise: the following is valid.
Where x is an integer,
where y is the same integer, x plus y is y plus x.
Where x is an integer, where y is a different integer, x plus y
is y plus x.
Where x is an integer,
where y is an integer, x plus y is y plus x.
The earlier it is in the course the more
important it is for the teacher to explicitly draw the obvious conclusions,
which are often eye-openers to the students: in this case the point to make is
that the two premises of the last argument taken together are logically
equivalent to the conclusion. The two premises just divide up the information
in the conclusion; drawing the conclusion puts the information back together into
one proposition, so to speak. (See Corcoran, 1995:
“Information recovery problems”).
However some students will guess, especially when
helped with some Socratic questioning, that the commutativity
proposition expressed by C2 beginning with the plural quantifier ‘Where x and y
are integers’—taken literally—does not imply:
(+0 + -0) = (-0 + +0).
In other words, they will guess that the following
premise-conclusion argument, A1 below, is invalid—if the premise’s sentence is
read literally. Taken literally, the expression ‘where x and y are integers’
means the same as ‘where x and y are different integers’. In cases when
writers use it figuratively and do not want ‘different’ to be read in, they
often add ‘not necessarily distinct’. This brings a new set of interpretational
problems: ‘distinct’ is not an adjective expressing a property of distinctness;
it is elliptical for ‘numerically distinct’ expressing the relation of
numerical distinctness and the whole added phrase is short for ‘not necessarily
numerically distinct from each other’. This interesting and important semantic
issue plays no further role below.
ARGUMENT
A1
Where x
and y are different integers, x plus y is y plus x
+0
plus -0 is -0 plus +0
Continuing
their train of thought, they will guess or maybe claim that the following is
invalid.
ARGUMENT
A2
Where x
and y are different integers, x plus y is y plus x
Where
x and y are the same integer, x
plus y is y plus x
[20]
After
all, some will say, each of the following arguments has a true premise but a
false conclusion.
ARGUMENT
B1
Where x
and y are different integers, x exceeds y or y exceeds x
+0
exceeds -0 or -0 exceeds +0
ARGUMENT
B2
Where x
and y are different integers, x exceeds y or y exceeds x
Where
x and y are the same integer, x
exceeds y or y exceeds x
In teaching, whenever an invalidity
claim or guess is made, especially if it not obvious to everyone in the class,
a counterargument should be given—preferably elicited from the class. Trying to
find a counterargument for an argument that appears invalid can lead to a
realization that appearances can be misleading and that the argument is
actually valid. Notice that argument B1 is a counterargument to every other
argument in its same form and to itself. The same holds for B2.
But B1 is not in the same form as A1: B1 has a
relation “exceeds” but no operation, whereas A1 has an operation “plus” but no
relation. They are however instances of one and the same neutrovalid
schema: S1 below.
ARGUMENT
SCHEMA S1
Where x
and y are integers, R(x, y)
R(a, b)
For background experience, it is worth noting the
validity of two other arguments.
Where x
and y are different integers, x plus y is y plus x
if +0 isn’t -0, then +0 plus -0 is -0 plus
+0
Where x
and y are different integers, x plus y is y plus x
Where
x is an integer, x plus y is y plus x, where y is an integer
other than x
That being said a student might like to be reminded
that the following is also valid.
Where x
and y are different integers, x plus y is y
plus x
where x is an integer, x plus x is x plus x
But
the following is invalid, although +0 is -0.
Where x
is an integer, x plus x is x
plus x
+0
plus -0 is -0 plus +0
Of course if the premise is changed by adding ‘and
+0 is -0’, the new argument would be valid. Judging the old argument as if it
were the new would be the fallacy of premise-smuggling. (See
Corcoran, 1989). The invalidity of the above is shown using the
following counterargument.
Where x
is an integer, x minus x is x
minus x
+4
minus √4 is √4 minus +4
Deduction of the conclusion of Argument
A1 from its premise, thereby establishing its validity, is a very easy
exercise. Hint: take the tautology ‘+0 is -0 or +0 isn’t -0’ as the first line
and use disjunctive reasoning. Once A1 is deduced, by adapting the same ideas,
deducing Argument A2 will be easy. In a paper such as this, it is worth
mentioning explicitly that ‘deducing an argument’ means “deducing its
conclusion from its premise set”—as is natural and handy.
This discussion will give the instructor
the opportunity to reiterate four important points. The first is that many
excellent logic texts—including the influential 1934 Cohen-Nagel Introduction and even Tarski’s 1941 masterpiece—treat plurals as singulars—and
without a word of warning (Cohen-Nagel, 1934/1993: 42ff; Tarski,
1941/1995; 7ff).
The second is that literal reading of double universal quantifications expressed
using pluralized range indicators—e. g.,
‘where x and y are integers’— is closely related to the “separated-variables”
reading of double universal quantifications expressed using singular range indicators—‘where x [21] is a number and y is a number’. The separated-variables
reading takes the values assigned to the two variables to be two distinct
numbers almost as if ‘where x is a
number and y is a number’ were read
as elliptical for ‘where x is a
number and y is a different number’.
One reason for bringing this up is that some students are inclined to take it
that way naturally—and thus to be out of touch with the class. I noticed this
in my own teaching as have other logic teachers including Albert Visser (personal communication). Another reason is that
Wittgenstein adopted a separated-variables approach in his 1922 Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.
The third point the instructor can make
is that finding inattention or even inaccuracy in a work is no evidence that
alertness and exactness, perhaps even brilliant creativity is not to be found
in it also. Don’t throw the baby out with the bathwater. But, don’t put the
bathwater in the crib with the baby.
This reminds me of what Frango Nabrasa calls “Newton’s
Law of Fallacies”: for every fallacy there’s an equal and opposite fallacy.
Trying too hard to avoid one lands you in the other.
Falling backward is not a good way to avoid falling forward. “Political
correctness” is not a good way to avoid ethnic, race, religion, philosophy, or
gender insensitivity.
The fourth point, minor to the expert
but eye-opening to the beginner, is that every integer has infinitely many
names even if we don’t count those made by adding any number of plus signs and
those made by adding any even number of minus signs: 0 = - -0, 0 = - - - -0,
etc.
This is a natural place to describe the
pluralisms in logic that I advocate. The one I had in mind when I made the
abstract and table of contents concerns awareness of the variety of classical
logics actually used as underlying logics in traditional disciplines. In 1974 I
discussed this pluralism and its role in historical research. See my 1974
“Future Research on Ancient Theories of Communication and Reasoning”. The most
important variety of classical logic by far is standard one-sorted, first-order
logic. But many-sorted logic and higher-order logics are essential. See my 2001
“Second-order logic”. Moreover, varieties of identity logics are useful for
understanding the logical experiences students have in their algebra courses.
See the 1979 “Identity logics” and the 2015 “Teaching basic logics”. We may
call this classical pluralism:
recognizing the variety of classical logics that can serve as underlying logics
humans actually use in their intellectual lives.
Another form of pluralism I have advocated
may be called disciplinary pluralism.
This is the [22] recognition that in the development of the many
disciplines—arithmetic, geometry, set theory, etc.—there is no
“one-size-fits-all” underlying logic; rather each classical discipline has its
own classical underlying logic. For example, the logic of arithmetic differs
from that of geometry in several ways. One metamathematically
important way is that arithmetic has proper names for all of its objects but
geometry has proper names for none of its objects—a point I learned from Tarski. See, for example, my 1973 “Gaps between logical
theory and mathematical practice”.
Applying this philosophy to teaching excludes presentation to undergraduates
of “superlogics” such as the “functional calculus of
first order” in Section 30 of Church (1956). These logics were constructed to
achieve a maximum of generality but the result is alienating artificiality and
ugly clutter. They have infinitely many classes of primitive symbols and each
class is infinite. For example, for each number n, there are infinitely many
n-placed predicate symbols. It would take years of study for a student to be
able to see such “classical” logics as responding to any goal in classical
logic implicit in the tradition founded by Aristotle. This kind of exclusion
applies to many other “classical” logics including those in Tarski
1941/1995 and Quine
(1970). I recommend that teachers avoid idiosyncratic, exotic, esoteric,
artificial, unintuitive, or overly general forms of classical, Aristotelian,
two-valued logics—call them what you want—to undergraduates. Try logics that
help the student to discover logical reality and to get in touch with their own
inner logician.
Another form of pluralism I have
advocated may be called analytical
pluralism. This is the recognition that many a natural-language sentence
used in a given discipline may be used to express different propositions and
thus admit of a plurality of analyses: there is no “one-size-fits-all” logical
analysis for a given sentence. Rather in each context one must do a new
analysis—sometimes more than one in the same context. The question “what is the
logical form of this sentence?” makes the usually-false presupposition that
“this sentence” has only one logical form. We should ask “what are the logical
forms of the propositions expressed by this sentence?”.
For the record, I do not advocate
teaching exotic, esoteric, non-classical, non-Aristotelian, deviant logics—call
them what you want—to undergraduates who have not mastered articulations of
their own inner logics. See Quine 1970 on deviant logics. This would be
like teaching non-Euclidean geometries to students who had not yet developed
their classical Euclidean intuitions. Maybe it would be more like teaching
“languages” that were never used for communication and never will be. Again,
perhaps it would be like feeding unhealthy commercial snacks to children who
were still struggling to appreciate healthy home-cooked foods. There are other
analogies that are even more negative.
Anyway, the pluralism that advocates
teaching exotic non-classical logic to beginners is one I find
counter-productive or worse. It alienates students from logical reality and
prevents them from learning the logic they need in their lives. I call it adventurist pluralism.
That said, I
hasten to add that I am far from condemning non-classical logics. That
non-classical logics play fruitful roles in modern logical research is well
established, as is explained, for example, in my 1973 “Gaps between logical
theory and mathematical practice”.
Moreover, notice that I have not said classical logics are perfect
models of human logical competence. On the contrary, I have said that they are not and how they are not—in the 1973 paper just
mentioned and elsewhere—a point I will return to in my Conclusion below.
Moreover, let us not forget that our
basic mathematical sciences presuppose classical underlying logics. For
example, in number theory the great proofs including that of Fermat’s Last
Theorem use classical logic. Also, in mathematical logic, proofs of the great
meta-theorems of Gödel, Tarski, Craig, and Henkin were not only classical in their reasoning but they
were about classical logics.
Let us wrap up the discussion of commutativity
and associativity by explaining how their
independence is established using the method of counterarguments as described
in various places including Corcoran (1989). The first step is to express them
in full explicitly using a range-indicator: ‘I’ for ‘integer’. To show that commutativity does not follow from associativity,
consider the following.
∀Ix∀Iy∀Iz(x
+ (y + z)) = ((x + y) + z)
∀Ix∀Iy(x
+ y) = (y + x)
The
goal is to produce another argument in the same logical form with a premise
known to be true and a conclusion known to be false.
For
our universe of discourse, or range of values of our variables, we choose the
strings of letters of the alphabet and take ‘S’, abbreviating ‘String’, as our
range-indicator. Thus ‘∀Sx’
means “for every string x”. For our
two-place operation corresponding to addition we take concatenation: the result
of concatenating the two-character string ‘ab’ to the
three-character string ‘cde’ is the five-character
string ‘abcde’. Using the made-up word ‘concat’ for this operation, we can say that ‘ab’ concat ‘cde’
is ‘abcde’. Using the arch ‘ᴖ’
for “concat”, we have the equation (identity):
‘ab’ ᴖ ‘cde’ = ‘abcde’
Our
counterargument is thus the following.
∀Sx∀Sy∀Sz(x ᴖ (y ᴖ z)) = ((x ᴖ y) ᴖ z)
∀Sx∀Sy(x
ᴖ y) = (y ᴖ x)
A
little thought about strings reveals the truth of the premise. The falsity of
the conclusion is seen by noting that it implies the following.
[23]
‘ab’ ᴖ ‘cde’ = ‘cde’ ᴖ‘ab’
But,
‘abcde’ isn’t ‘cdeab’: the
first begins with ‘a’, but the second begins with ‘c’. Similar deliberations show
that commutativity does not imply associativity.
The
method of counterarguments was routinely and repeatedly used in practice almost
instinctively before the theory used to describe it was developed. In fact, the
method came before anyone mentioned logical forms of arguments. Indeed, the
definition of being-in-the-same-form-as is of recent origin. See “Logical form”
in Audi (2015). One of the theoretical principles presupposed by this method is
that in order for an argument to be valid it is necessary and sufficient for
every argument in the same form to be valid.
In
teaching, the order of presentation should follow the historical order of
discovery—at least this is a point Tarski stressed.
§6.
Logical propositions, arguments, deductions, and counterarguments
But
many mathematicians seem to have so little feeling for logical purity and
accuracy that they will use a word to stand for three or four different things,
sooner than make the frightful decision to invent a new word.
—Frege
1893/1967, Sect. 60
A
further welcome development is the separation of laws of logic from so-called
logical truths, i.e., tautologies. Now we can teach the logical independence of
the laws of excluded middle and noncontradiction
without fear that students had been indoctrinated into thinking that every
logical law was a tautology and that every falsehood of logic was a
contradiction. This separation permits the logic teacher to apply logic in the
clarification of laws of logic.
Before
treating the content of this topic it is necessary to reveal an embarrassing
feature of the literature of logic. When a publication uses a familiar
expression, the writer has certain responsibilities to the reader. Moreover
when those responsibilities are not met, reviewers have the responsibility to
point this out and to criticize the publication. The expressions of immediate
relevance are the law of
non-contradiction—some say contradiction,
without the non—and the law of excluded-middle—some say excluded-third. Use of these without further explanation,
especially in introductory contexts, presupposes that those expressions have
fixed, generally agreed upon meanings and that the reader knows what those
meanings are. Even if the publication explicitly says what these expressions
are taken to denote, it is still inexcusably misleading not to warn the reader
that these expressions have been used over centuries in many, perhaps a dozen
or more, ways. Even worse, different senses are associated with different
philosophies of logic.
Take
the expression the law of contradiction.
For centuries the ambiguous expression
Law of contradiction (or non-contradiction)
denoted (1) assertoric propositions such as
No proposition is both true and false,
(2) modalized
versions with ‘can be’ for ‘is’— and (3)
very different modals such as
It is impossible that a property belonging to an individual at a
time does not belong to the individual at that same time.
This gives us three classes of uses, each containing
two or more variants. But these three have been confused with others, three of
which are mentioned here.
(4)
No
proposition is such that it and its negation are both true.
(5)
No
proposition is such that it and its contradictory are both true.
(6)
No
proposition is both true and not true.
[24]
However, Boole used the expression for
an equation in class algebra, thus
creating a seventh class of referents (Corcoran-Legault,
2013). This ambiguity persisted for decades—as Cohen and Nagel’s popular and
influential 1934 Introduction
attests.
Using terminology from Tarski’s
Introduction, the first class has the
variant:
No sentence is both true and false.
This law is unmistakably presupposed
throughout Tarski’s Chapters I and II, especially in
Section 13 about truth-tables. Astoundingly, no such sentence occurs in Tarski’s Introduction.
Also conspicuously missing is an explicit
statement that no sentential-function is satisfied and not satisfied by the
same object. Absence of reference to any traditional law in Chapters I and II
suggests the hypothesis that Tarski deliberately
avoided mentioning it.
Another curious fact is that Tarski’s
Section 13 appropriated the expression Law
of contradiction for a law which doesn’t involve the words true and false or even symbolic renderings thereof—creating an eighth class
of senses. Tarski abbreviated the law:
~[ p ˄ (~p)]
Stated fully using Tarski’s
instructions (3,Section 13).
for any sentence p, ~[ p ˄ (~p)]
Another peculiarity is that Tarski avoids any clues about English translations of this
perplexing sentence: its variables’s values are
exactly the same as their substituents—a peculiarity
making the sentence difficult if not impossible to grasp. Having a variable’s
values being its substituents is a kind of
use-mention conflation: a variable’s substituents are
used to mention its values. For example, in arithmetic, the individual
variables have numbers as values and numerals as substituents:
the number zero is a value of the variable having the numeral ‘0’ as a
substituent. Values are things in the universe of discourse of an interpreted
language; substituents are names in that language.
Tarski’s writing suggests, especially to
beginners, that this strange and perplexing expression is what is normally
called the law of contradiction.
Having dispensed some of our
terminological responsibilities, let us turn to the main topic of this Section.
The law of non-contradiction—“no proposition is both true and false”—and the
law of excluded-middle—“every proposition is either true or false”—are both
laws of logic but neither is a tautology, or logical truth in the broad sense.
Every proposition in the same form as a tautology is a tautology and therefore
a truth. But each of those two laws is in the same form as falsehoods: “no
triangle is both equilateral and equiangular” is false and so is “every
triangle is either equilateral or equiangular”.
People who think that every law of logic is a
tautology are apt to think that, since all tautologies are logically
equivalent, all laws of logic are logically equivalent. But to see that noncontradiction doesn’t imply excluded-middle it is
sufficient to see that the following argument is invalid.
every proposition is
either true or false
To see that this argument is invalid it is
sufficient to see that it has a counterargument: an argument in the same form
with a true premise and false conclusion.
every integer is
either positive or negative
To see that a universal proposition is
false it is sufficient to see that it has a counterexample: in this case an
object that satisfies the subject but dissatisfies the predicate. Zero is an integer that is not either positive or negative.
Thus noncontradiction
does not imply excluded-middle. In other words, excluded-middle does not follow
from noncontradiction; the argument having noncontradiction as its only premise and excluded-middle as
its conclusion is invalid.
The same method shows that
excluded-middle does not imply noncontradiction.
[25]
Incidentally, this example illustrates
the importance of distinguishing counterargument from counterexample. But, this
should not be taken to imply that no counterarguments are counterexamples. On
the contrary, every counterargument for a given argument is a counterexample to
the universal proposition that every argument in the same form as the given
argument is valid.
Once methods and results have been presented, some
succinct exercises are needed. Preferable exercises are that (1) maximize
creative use of what has been learned and that (2) minimize writing. For these
and other related reasons, alternative-constituent format questions are often
appropriate. Here is one relevant example.
The law of (excluded-middle * noncontradiction)
is logically equivalent to “every proposition that (is not * is) true (is not *
is) false”.
Alternative-constituent exercises can often be made
more demanding as exemplified below.
The law of (excluded-middle * noncontradiction)
is logically equivalent to “every proposition that (is not * is) (true *false)
(is not * is) (false * true)”.
The law of (excluded-middle * noncontradiction)
is logically (equivalent to * independent of) “every proposition that (is not *
is) (true *false) (is not * is) (false * true)”.
Further discussion and application of the
alternative-constituent format is found in my 2008 “Meanings of form”
(Corcoran, 2009, and Corcoran-Main (2011).
Conclusion
As is evident by now to many readers,
this essay does not intend to be definitive or comprehensive. It is more like a
contribution to a dialogue. What did I leave out? Every reader will have an
answer.
One glaring omission is the importance
of memorization. My logical life has been enriched by reflecting on texts that
I had memorized. Students have only the fuzziest idea of what the axiomatic
method is unless they know of concrete examples. The first step in acquiring objectual knowledge of an axiom system is to memorize one.
I require my students to memorize two axiom systems for arithmetic: the five Peano postulates and the three Gödel axioms used in his
1931 incompleteness paper. See the Editor’s
Introduction to Cohen-Nagel 1934/1993: Introduction
to Logic. Once concrete examples are before the mind many questions come into
focus and axiomatic method is promoted from being a topic of loose conversation
to being an object for investigation.
I also recommend memorizing Euclid’s
axioms and postulates. These three examples of creative memorization are just
the beginning.
Another important topic that has not
been treated is something that has already been absorbed into logic teaching
and that doesn’t need to be recommended: teaching natural-deduction logic as
opposed to axiomatic logic.
If I had more time, I would discuss the
enormous mathematical, philosophical, and heuristic advantages of Jaśkowski -style sentential natural deduction. It is
impossible to exaggerate the importance of Jaśkowski’s
insights—especially in my own thinking and research: I use them almost every
day. See my three-part series Corcoran (1971) “Discourse Grammars and the
Structure of Mathematical Reasoning”.
Teaching a well-crafted, intuitive, and
user-friendly Jaśkowski-style sentential natural
deduction system can awaken a student’s sense of logical reality and overcome
the alienating effects of artificial approaches—truth-tables, trees, semantic
tableaux, sequent calculi, Turing-machine implementable algorithms, etc.
There have been several small but
important innovations in making natural deduction systems more natural. One is
the recognition that indirect deduction is a special form of deduction not to
be subsumed under negation intelim [sc.
introduction-and-elimination] rules. Another is the recognition that deduction
is a goal-directed activity and that goal-setting is an essential step. Both of
[26] these points are developed in my 2009 “Aristotle’s Demonstrative Logic”,
where special notational devices for indirect deduction and for goal-setting
appear in print for the first time. It would be a mistake of the sort already
criticized to think that currently available Jaśkowski-style
systems cannot be made more realistic and thus more user-friendly.
Artificial approaches based on axiomatic logics,
sequent logics, tree-logics, and the like are out of place in undergraduate
logic. Such systems, of course, have their legitimate mathematical uses. For an
interesting discussion, see Dummett (1973: 430ff).
Moreover, knowledge of some of them is essential not only for certain advanced
research but also for understanding the history of logic and the evolution of
philosophy of logic. Nevertheless, as Michael Dummett
emphasized in regard to axiomatic logics, their artificiality needs to be
exposed so that a false view of logic is not conveyed as an officially-condoned
viewpoint (Dummett, 1973: 432-434).
Acknowledgements
An earlier version of this paper was
written for presentation to the 18th
International Conference of Logic Teaching (XVIII EIDL 2015) under the
auspices of the Mexican Academy of Logic (AML). It was delivered on 10 November
2015 in the University of Guadalajara’s Auditorio
Salvador Allende. The next day it was the focus of a
two-hour seminar. It owes its existence to the organizers of the conference,
especially to Professor Jesús Jasso
Méndez. Suggestions, corrections, and sympathetic
criticism from the audience at the time and through later correspondence
materially improved its present form. That said, the thinking that led up to
this paper was advanced significantly in writing my 2010 “Los primeros días de todo curso de Lógica”.
Many thanks to Edgar Andrade, Timothy Biehler, Mark Brown, James Cargile,
Julian Cole, Joseph Corcoran, Itala D’Ottaviano, Ralph Gillmann,
Rolando Gripaldo, Idris Samawi Hamid, Leonard Jacuzzo, John Keller, Fernando Leal, Justin Legault, Hassan Masoud, Jesús Jasso Méndez,
Joaquin Miller, Raymundo Morado,
Sriram Nambiar, Daniel
Novotny, Joseph Paterno, Paul Penner,
Robert Rovetto, José Miguel Sagüillo,
Guido Slacucchi, Michael Scanlan,
James Smith, Kevin Tracy, Albert Visser, Vlastimil Vohánka, George Weaver,
Jeffrey Welaish, and others. Special thanks for
special contributions to Mark Brown, Idris Samawi Hamid, Fernando Leal,
Hassan Masoud, Jesús Jasso Méndez, Sriram
Nambiar, and Kevin Tracy.
Logic research in the 21st century is becoming more
and more a communal activity as opposed to the solitary personal activity it
was in the past. Before this century, with very rare exceptions, logical works
were single-authored. In this century multiple-authored works are common and
even single-authored works often have an acknowledgements section listing
colleagues that contributed. Moreover, logic research in the 21st century is
also becoming more and more an international activity. In fact, in this century
we have multiple-authored works for which the authors are from different
countries. Finally, logic research in the 21st century is becoming more and
more interdisciplinary: logicians are listening more to the criticisms of logic
made by their colleagues and logicians are responding to the logical needs of a
broader community.
[27]
References
Works
cited
Audi,
R. (ed.) (2015). Cambridge
Dictionary of Philosophy (third edition).
Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Boole,
G. (1854/2003). The Laws of Thought (facsimile of 1854
edition, with an introduction by J. Corcoran). Buffalo: Prometheus
Books.
Church,
A. (1956). Introduction
to Mathematical Logic. Princeton: Princeton UP.
Cohen,
M. and E. Nagel (1934/1993).
Introduction to Logic (second
edition, revised with new exercises, new indices, a new bibliography, and a
30-page introduction by J. Corcoran).
Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
Corcoran,
J. (1972). “Harris on the Structures of Language”. In Transformationelle Analyse (pp.
275292) (ed. Senta Plötz).
Frankfurt: Athenäum Verlag.
Corcoran,
J., W. Frank and M. Maloney. (1974). String Theory. Journal
of Symbolic Logic 39,
625-37. MR0398771 (53 #2622).
Corcoran,
J. and J. Swiniarski (1978).
Logical Structures of Ockham’s Theory of Supposition. Franciscan Studies, 38, 161-183.
Dummett, M. (1973).
Frege: Philosophy of Language. New York:
Harper and Row.
Frege, G. (1893/1967).
The Basic Laws of
Arithmetic (M. Furth, translator). Berkeley: UC Press.
Galen. (200? /1964). Institutio Logica. (Trs.
and ed. J. Kieffer). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP.
Grice, P. (1989). Studies in the Way of Words.
Cambridge MA: Harvard UP.
Kneale, W. and M. Kneale.
(1962). Development of
logic. Oxford: Oxford UP.
Lachs, J. and R. Talisse
(eds.) (2007). American Philosophy: an Encyclopedia. New York: Routledge.
Quine,
W. O. (1940). Mathematical
logic. New York: Harper-Row.
Quine,
W. O. (1970). Philosophy
of logic. Cambridge: Harvard UP.
Quine,
W. O. (1987). Peano as logician. History
and Philosophy of Logic, 8, 15-24.
Quintilian.
(96?/1920). Institutio Oratoria. (Trans. H.E. Butler). Cambridge: Harvard UP.
Russell,
B. (1922). Introduction
to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.
London: Kegan Paul.
Sagüillo,
J. M. (1999). “Domains of sciences, universe of discourse,
and omega arguments”. In History and philosophy of logic, vol. 20 (pp. 267-280).
Tarski, A. (1941/1995). Introduction to Logic. New York:
Dover.
Tarski, A. and S. Givant.
(1987). A Formalization
of Set Theory without Variables. Providence: American Mathematical
Society.
Watts,
I. (1725/1790). Logick. London: Buckland et al.
William
of Ockham. (1330?/1990).
Philosophical Writings (Philotheus Boehner, translator), Indianapolis:
Hackett.
Wittgenstein,
L. (1922). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.
London: Kegan Paul.
[28]
Logic-teaching
articles by John Corcoran
(1971a).
Discourse Grammars and the Structure of Mathematical Reasoning I: Mathematical Reasoning and Stratification of Language. Journal of Structural Learning 3(1),
55-74.
(1971b).
Discourse Grammars and the Structure of Mathematical Reasoning II: The Nature
of a Correct Theory of Proof and Its Value. Journal
of Structural Learning, 3(2), 1-16.
(1971c).
Discourse Grammars and the Structure of Mathematical Reasoning III: Two
Theories of Proof. Journal of Structural
Learning 3(3), 1-24.
(1972a).
Conceptual Structure of Classical Logic.
Philosophy & Phenomenological
Research, 33, 25-47.
(1972b).
Strange Arguments. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 13, 206-210. MR0297513 (45 #6567).
(1972c).
Review of Quine 1970 “Philosophy of Logic”.
Philosophy of Science, 39, 97-99.
(1973a).
“Gaps between logical theory and mathematical practice”.
In M. Bunge (ed.)
Methodological Unity of Science (pp. 23-50). Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Co.
(1973b).
Meanings of Implication. Diálogos, 9, 59-76. MR95c:03019.
(1974).
“Future Research on Ancient Theories of Communication and Reasoning”.
In J. Corcoran (ed.). Ancient Logic and Its Modern Interpretations (pp. 185-187).
Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Co. MR0485116 (58 #4971).
(1979).
Identity Logics. (Co-author: Steven Ziewacz). Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 20, 777-84. MR0545427 (80h:
03017)
(1980).
Boole’s Criteria of Validity and Invalidity (Co-author: S. Wood). Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 21,
609-39. MR0592521 (81j:03003).
(1989a).
Argumentations and Logic. Argumentation, 3, 17-43. MR91b:03006
(1989b).
Significados de la Implicación.
Agora, 5, 279-294. (Spanish
translation by J. M. Sagüillo of “Meanings of
Implication”).
(1989c).
The Inseparability of Logic and Ethics. Free Inquiry. Spring, 37-40.
(1994).
Argumentaciones y lógica.
Agora, 13(1), 27-55. (Translation by R. Fernández and J. Sagüillo of revised and expanded version of “Argumentations
and Logic”).
(1995,
september). Information recovery problems. Theoria, 10, 55-78. MR1361162 (96h: 03016)
(1995).
Semantic Arithmetic: a Preface. Agora,
14(1), 149-156.
(1998).
“Information-theoretic logic”. In C. Martínez, U. Rivas and L. Villegas-Forero
(eds.). Truth in
Perspective (pp. 113-135). Aldershot, England: Ashgate Publishing Limited.
(1999).
Critical thinking and pedagogical license.
Manuscrito, 22, 109-116.
(2001).
“Second-order Logic”. In M. Zeleny and C. A. Anderson (eds.).
“Church Memorial Volume”, Logic, Meaning, and Computation: Essays in
Memory of Alonzo Church (pp. 61-76). Dordrecht, Holland: Kluwer Publishing Company. MR2067966 (2005a:03021)
(2003).
Aristotle’s Prior Analytics and Boole’s Laws of Thought.
History and Philosophy of Logic, 24, 261-288.
(2006a).
C. I. Lewis: History and Philosophy of Logic. Transactions of the C. S. Peirce Society, 42, 1-9.
(2006b).
Schemata: the Concept of Schema in the History of Logic. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 12, 219-40.
(2008).
Meanings of Form. Manuscrito, 31, 223-266.
(2009).
Aristotle’s Demonstrative Logic.
History and Philosophy of Logic, 30,
1-20. Reviewed MR2488682 (2009m:03003).
(2009).
“Sentence, Proposition, Judgment, Statement, and Fact: Speaking about the
Written English Used in Logic”. In W. A. Carnielli,
M. E. Coniglio and I. M. Loffredo
D’ Ottaviano (eds.). The Many [29] Sides of Logic (pp. 71-103). (Series “Studies in Logic”). London: College Publications. MR2777861 (2012a:03010)
(2010). Los primeros días de todo curso de Lógica. Ergo. Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad
Veracruzana, 25, 31-45. (Spanish
translation by Patricia Diaz-Herrera of an unpublished paper “The first days of
every logic course”).
(2011). Hare and Others on the Proposition.
Principia, 15(1), 51-76.
(2014).
Existential import today: New metatheorems;
historical, philosophical, and pedagogical misconceptions. History and Philosophy of Logic, 36, 39-61. (Co-author: Hassan Masoud). Published online 25 Sep 2014.
DOI:10.1080/01445340.2014.952947
(2015a).
Existential-import mathematics. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 21, 1-14.
(Co-author: Hassan Masoud)
(2015b).
“Investigating knowledge and opinion”.
In A. Buchsbaum and A. Koslow
(eds.) The Road to Universal Logic, vol. I. (pp.
95-126). Basel: Springer. (Co-author Idris
Samawi Hamid).
[30]
Logic-teaching
abstracts by John Corcoran
(1981).
Ockham’s Syllogistic Semantics. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 46, 197-198.
(1997).
Teaching categoricity of arithmetic. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic,
3, 395.
(1999).
The logical form of quantifier phrases: quantifier-sortal-variable. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 5, 418-419.
(2000).
Self-defeating and self-fulfilling propositions.
Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 6, 111.
(2001).
What are logical relations?. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 7, 105-106.
(2004).
First-order Logical Form.
Bulletin of Symbolic Logic
10, 445.
(2005).
Meanings of word: type-occurrence-token. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 11,
117.
(2005).
Counterexamples and Proexamples. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 11, 460.
(2005).
Logically Equivalent False Universal Propositions with Different Counterexample
Sets. Bulletin of
Symbolic Logic, 11, 554-5.
(2006a).
Complete enumerative inductions. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 12, 165-66.
(2006b).
Meanings of Inference, Deduction, and Derivation.
Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 12,
353-354.
(2008a).
Aristotle’s many-sorted logic. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic.
14, 155–6.
(2008b).
Iffication, Preiffication, Qualiffication, Reiffication, and
Deiffication.
Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 14,
435-436.
(2009a).
Agent and Premise Implication. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic.
15, 235. (Co-author: K. Barber).
(2009b).
Alternative-Constituent Format. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic.
15, 133.
(2009c).
Ambiguity: Lexical and Structural. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 15,
235-6.
(2009d).
Consequence/consequent necessity.
Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 15, 461.
(2009e).
Premise-conclusion Arguments. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 15, 461.
(Co-author:
J. Miller)
(2009f). Self-denying
and self-affirming statements. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 15 (2009) 244.
(2009g). What is a proof?. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 15, 461-2. (Co-author: J. M. Sagüillo)
(2010).
Hidden consequence and hidden independence.
Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 16, 443.
(2011).
Numerically-indexed Alternative Constituent Format.
Bulletin of Symbolic Logic,
17, 152-3. (Co-author: R.
Main)
(2012a).
Implications of implication. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic.
18 (2012) 147–8. (Co-author: J. Donhauser)
(2012b).
Paracounterexamples: virtual counterexamples. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic.
18 (2012) 147.
(2012c).
Predicates and predications. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic,
18, 148. (Co-author: C. McGrath)
(2012d).
Quantifier-range-variable: the logical form of quantifications. Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 18, 471.
(2012e).
Refutation and proof. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 18, 473.
(Co-author: H. Masoud)
(2012f).
Truth-values and formal truth-value distributions of arguments. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 18, 148-9. (Co-author: S. Nambiar)
(2013a).
Aristotle, Boole, and Tarski on contradiction. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 19, 515.
(Co-author: J. Legault)
(2013b). “Deriving”
Euclid’s Interchange Rule from Leibniz’s Law.
Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 19, 507-8.
(2013c). Equality and
identity. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 19, 255-6.
(Co-author: A. Ramnauth)
(2013d). Errors in Tarski’s 1983 truth definition paper.
Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 19, 514.
(2013e).
Meta-language, object-language. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 19, 232-3.
(Co-author: I. Samawi Hamid)
(2013f).
Surprises in logic. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 19, 253. (Co-author: W. Frank)
[31]
(2013g).
Surprising universal para-counterexample numbers. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 19, 255. (Co-author:
S. Nambiar)
(2013h).
Verifying and falsifying. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 19, 509-10. (Co-author: H. Masoud)
(2014a).
Aristotelian logic and Euclidean geometry.
Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 20, 131. (Co-author: G. Boger)
(2014b).
Conversely: extrapropositional
and prosentential. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 20, 404.
(Co-author: S. Nambiar)
(2014c).
Cosmic Justice Hypotheses. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 20, 247-8.
(Co-author: W. Frank)
(2014d).
De Morgan on Euclid’s fourth postulate.
Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 20, 250. (Co-author: S. Nambiar)
(2014e).
Euclid’s weak first axiom. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 20, 405.
(Co-author: J. M. Sagüillo)
(2014f).
Meanings of hypothesis. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 20, 248-9.
(Co-authors: M. LaVine and J. Legault)
(2014g).
Meanings of show.
Bulletin of Symbolic Logic,
20, 403-4. (Co-author: J. Miller)
(2014h).
Objectivity-subjectivity distinctions.
Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 20, 248. (Co-author: I. Samawi Hamid)
(2014i).
Self-refuting propositions and self-sustaining propositions.
Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 20, 250. (Co-author: J. M. Sagüillo)
(2014j).
Truth-preserving and consequence-preserving deduction rules.
Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 20, 130-1.
(2015a).
Absence of argument-deduction-proof distinctions in Church 1956.
Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 21,
230-231.
(2015b).
Aristotle’s semiotic triangles and pyramids.
Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 21, 198.
(2015c).
Deductive and inductive arguments. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 21,
231-232. (Co-author: J. M. Sagüillo)
(2015d).
Expressing set-size equality. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 21,
239. (Co-author: G. Rising)
(2015e).
Implication and deduction.
Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 21, 238-239.
(Co-authors: H. Masoud and S. Nambiar)
(2015f).
Plato’s mathematical deductivism.
Bulletin of Symbolic
Logic, 21, 199. (Co-author: H. Masoud)
(2015g).
Teaching course-of-values induction. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 21,
101.
(2015h).
Teaching basic logics. Bulletin
of Symbolic Logic, 21, 364.
(2015i). Teaching independence. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 21, 101-102. (Co-author: J. M. Sagüillo)